Citations related to PHILOSOPHY
(works cited listed at bottom):
“So long as humanism is constructed through contrast with the object that
has been abandoned to epistemology, neither the human nor the nonhuman can
be understood.” Latour, Bruno. We Have Never Been Modern. Harvard
University Press. 1993. p. 136.
"Without serious, not to say obsessional monotheism and unitarianism, the
rationalist naturalism of the Enlightenment might well never have seen the
light of day. In all probability, the attachment to a unique Revelation
was the historical pre-condition of the successful emergence of a unique
and symmetrically accessible Nature. It was a jealous Jehovah who really
taught mankind the Law of the Excluded Middle: Greek formalization of
logic (and geometry and grammar) probably would not have been sufficient
on its own. Without a strong religious impulsion towards a single orderly
world, and the consequent avoidance of opportunist, manipulative
incoherence, the cognitive miracle would probably not have occurred." Gellner, Ernest, Postmodernism, Reason and Religion, Routledge, 1992, pp.
95-6.
“Moment by moment and situation by situation, each person is moving
through a continuum of interaction rituals, real or vicarious, ranging
from minimal to high intensity, which bring in a flow of cultural capital
and calibrate their emotional energy up or down. These local situations
are embedded in a larger structure: in this case the whole intellectual
community, spreading as far as the networks happen to extend in that
historical period.” Collins, Randall. The Sociology of Philosophies: A
Global Theory of Intellectual Change. Belknap Press of Harvard University
Press. 1999. p. 37.
“The intellectual world at its most intense has the structure of
contending groups, meshing together into a conflictual super-community.”
Collins, Randall. The Sociology of Philosophies: A Global Theory of
Intellectual Change. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. 1999. p.
73.
“Neither totalizing structures that repress differences nor oppositional
differences that exclude commonality are adequate in the plurality of
worlds that constitute the postmodern condition. To think what
post-structuralism leaves unthought is to think a nontotalizing structure
that nonetheless acts as a whole. Such a structure would be neither a
universal grid organizing opposites nor a dialectical system synthesizing
opposites but a seamy web in which what comes together is held apart and
what is held apart comes together. This web is neither subjective nor
objective and yet is the matrix in which all subjects and objects are
formed, deformed, and reformed. In the postmodern culture of simulacra, we
are gradually coming to realize that complex communication webs and
information networks, which function holisticaly but not totalisticaly,
are the milieu in which everything arises and passes away.” Taylor, Mark
C. The Moment of Complexity: Emerging Network Culture. University of
Chicago. 2001. p. 11.
“... it is simply wrong to insist that all systems and structures
necessarily totalize and inevitably repress. What Derrida cannot imagine
is a nontotalizing system or structure that nonetheless acts as a whole.
Taylor, Mark C. The Moment of Complexity: Emerging Network Culture.
University of Chicago. 2001. p. 65.
"According to the meta-physical framework of contextual realism, reality
consists of seemingly inexhaustible levels of semi-autonomous (or 'real')
contexts exhibiting a myriad of forms, properties, structures, and
processes. Analogous to the innumerable cellular structures disclosed at
successive levels by various staining techniques as seen under different
optical resolutions through a microscope, the world resolves into endless
matrices of relatively stable contexts exhibiting phenomena subject to
varying descriptive predicates and explanatory principles. Although these
multifarious contexts with their various structures are not entirely
discontinuous (otherwise our knowledge of them would be much more
difficult than it already is), neither are they merely successive
dimensions of essentially the same complexes of elements, as was assumed
in the past. Though manifesting some analogous relations and properties,
still, the forms and processes of the macroscopic world are not
qualitatively similar to those of the atomic-molecular domain, and the
conjugate properties of the latter, according to quantum mechanics, are
not repeated on the subatomic level. Moreover, as one moves outward to
cosmic, as opposed to inner atomic dimensions, one finds that the
structural relations between space and time, force fields and mass, or
gravitational fields and the space-time continuum become radically
altered, as described in the general theory of relativity. Schlagel,
Richard H., Contextual Realism; A Meta-physical Framework for Modern
Science, Paragon, 1986, pp. 274-5
"Despite the unsatisfactory state of mathematics, the variety of
approaches, the disagreements on acceptable axioms, and the danger that
new contradictions, if discovered, would invalidate a great deal of
mathematics, some mathematicians are still applying mathematics to
physical phenomena and indeed extending the applied fields to economics,
biology, and sociology. The continuing effectiveness of mathematics
suggests two themes. The first is that effectiveness can be used as the
criterion of correctness. Of course such a criterion is provisional. What
is considered correct today may prove wrong in the next application.
The second theme deals with a mystery. In view of the disagreements about
what sound mathematics is, why is it effective at all? Are we performing
miracles with imperfect tools? If man has been deceived, can nature also
be deceived into yielding to man's mathematical dictates? Clearly not.
Yet, do not our successful voyages to the moon and our explorations of
Mars and Jupiter, made possible by technology which itself depends heavily
on mathematics, confirm mathematical theories of the cosmos? How can we,
then, speak of the artificiality and varieties of mathematics? Can the
body live on when the mind and spirit are bewildered? Certainly this is
true of human beings and it is true of mathematics." Kline, Morris,
Mathematics: The Loss of Certainty, Oxford University Press, 1980, pps.
7-8.
"Lockean natural man, who is really identical to his civil man, whose
concern with comfortable self-preservation makes him law-abiding and
productive, is not all that natural. Rousseau quickly pointed out that
Locke, in his eagerness to find a simple or automatic solution to the
political problem, made nature do much more than he had a right to expect
a mechanical, nonteleological nature to do. Natural man would be brutish,
hardly distinguishable from any of the other animals, unsociable and
neither industrious nor rational, but, instead, idle and nonrational,
motivated exclusively by feelings or sentiments. Having cut off the higher
aspirations of man, those connected with the soul, Hobbes and Locke hoped
to find a floor beneath him, which Rousseau removed. Man tumbled down into
what I have called the basement, which now appears bottomless. And there,
down below, Rousseau discovered all the complexity in man that, in the
days before Machiaveli, was up on high. Locke had illegitimately selected
those parts of man he needed for his social contract and suppressed all
the rest, a theoretically unsatisfactory procedure and practically costly
one. The bourgeois is the measure of the price paid, he who most of all
cannot afford to look to his real self, who denies the existence of the
thinly boarded-over basement in him, who is most made over for the
purposes of a society that does not even promise him perfection or
salvation but merely buys him off. Rousseau explodes the simplistic
harmoniousness between nature and society that seems to be the American
premise.
"Rousseau still hoped for a soft landing on nature's true grounds, but one
not easily achieved, requiring both study and effort. The existence of
such a natural ground has become doubtful, and it is here that the abyss
opened up. But it was Rousseau who founded the modern psychology of the
self in its fullness, with its unending search for what is really
underneath the surface of rationality and civility, its new ways of
reaching the unconscious, and its unending task of constituting some kind
of healthy harmony between above and below.
"Rousseau's intransigence set the stage for a separation of man from
nature. He was perfectly willing to go along with the modern scientific
understanding that a brutish being is true man. But nature cannot
satisfactorily account for his difference from the other brutes, for his
movement from nature to society, for his history. Descartes, playing his
part in the dismantling of the soul, had reduced nature to extension,
leaving out of it only the ego that observes extension. Man is, in
everything but his consciousness, part of extension. Yet how he is a man,
a unity, what came to be called a self, is utterly mysterious. This
experienced whole, a combination of extension and ego, seems inexplicable
or groundless. Body, or atoms in motion, passions, and reason are some
kind of unity, but one that stands outside of the grasp of natural
science. Locke appears to have invented the self to provide unity in
continuity for the ceaseless temporal succession of sense impressions that
would disappear into nothingness if there were no place to hold them. We
can know everything in nature except that which knows nature. To the
extent that man is a piece of nature, he disappears. The self gradually
separates itself from nature, and its phenomena must be treated
separately. Descartes' ego, in appearance invulnerable and godlike in its
calm and isolation, turns out to be the tip of an iceberg floating in a
fathomless and turbulent sea called the id, consciousness an epiphenomenon
of the unconscious. Man is self, that now seems clear. But what is self?"
Bloom, Allan, The Closing of the American Mind, Simon & Schuster, 1987,
pp. 176-8.
"The term 'paradigm' enters the preceding pages early, and its manner of
entry is intrinsically circular. A paradigm is what the members of a
scientific community share, and, conversely, a scientific community
consists of men who share a paradigm.... Scientific communities can and
should be isolated without prior recourse to paradigms; the latter can
then be discovered by scrutinizing the behavior of a given community's
members. If this book were being rewritten, it would therefore open with a
discussion of the community structure of science,... Most practicing
scientists respond at once to questions about their community
affiliations, taking for granted that responsibility for the various
current specialties is distributed among groups of at least roughly
determinate membership. I shall therefore here assume that more systematic
means for their identification will be found.
"A scientific community consists, on this view, of the practitioners of a
scientific specialty. To an extent unparalleled inn most other fields,
they have undergone similar educations and professional initiations; in
the process they have absorbed the same technical literature and drawn
many of the same lessons from it. Usually the boundaries of that standard
literature mark the limits of a scientific subject matter, and each
community ordinarily has a subject matter of its own. There are schools in
the sciences, communities, that is, which approach the same subject from
incompatible viewpoints. But they are far rarer there than in other
fields; they are always in competition; and their competition is usually
quickly ended. As a result, the members of scientific community see
themselves and are seen by others as the men uniquely responsible for the
pursuit of a set of shared goals, including the training of their
successors. Within such groups communication is relatively full and
professional judgment relatively unanimous. Because the attention of
different scientific communities is, on the other hand, focused on
different matters, professional communication across group lines is
sometimes arduous, often results in misunderstanding, and may, if pursued,
evoke significant and previously unsuspected disagreement.
"Turn now to paradigms and ask what they can possibly be. My original text
leaves no more obscure or important question.... (e.g., Newton's Laws are
sometimes a paradigm, sometimes parts of a paradigm, and sometimes
paradigmatic)...
"To that question my original text licenses the answer, a paradigm or set
of paradigms. But for this use, unlike the one to be discussed below, the
term is inappropriate. Scientists themselves would say they share a theory
or set of theories,... For present purposes I suggest 'disciplinary
matrix': 'disciplinary' because it refers to the common possession of the
practitioners of a particular discipline; 'matrix' because it is composed
of ordered elements of various sorts, each requiring further
specification. All or most of the objects of group commitment that my
original text makes paradigms, parts of paradigms, or paradigmatic are
constituents of the disciplinary matrix, and as such form a whole and
function together. Kuhn, Thomas, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions,
Second Edition, The University of Chicago Press, 1970, Postscript, pps.
176-7, 181-2.
"Americans are Lockeans: recognizing that work is necessary (no longing
for a nonexistent Eden), and will produce well-being; following their
natural inclinations moderately, not because they possess the virtue of
moderation but because their passions are balanced and they recognize the
reasonableness of that; respecting the rights of others so that theirs
will be respected; obeying the law because they made it in their own
interest. From the point of view of God or heroes, all this is not very
inspiring. But for the poor, the weak, the oppressed--the overwhelming
majority of mankind--it is the promise of salvation. As Leo Strauss put
it, the moderns 'built on low but solid ground.'
"Rousseau believed that Hobbes and Locke did not go far enough, that they
had not reached the Indies of the spirit, although they thought they had.
They found exactly what they set out to look for: a natural man whose
naturalness consisted in having just those qualities necessary to
constitute society. It was too simple to be true.
"'Natural man is entirely for himself. He is numerical unity, the absolute
whole which is relative only to itself or its kind. Civil man is only a
fractional unity dependent on the denominator, his value is determined by
his relation to the whole, which is the social body....
"'He who in the civil order wants to preserve the primacy of the
sentiments of nature does not know what he wants. Always in contradiction
with himself, always floating between his inclinations and his duties, he
will never be either man or citizen. He will be good neither for himself
nor for others. He will be one of these men of our days: a Frenchman, an
Englishman, a bourgeois. He will be nothing.'
"It was Locke who wanted to preserve the primacy of the sentiments of
nature in the civil order, and the result of his mistake is the bourgeois.
Rousseau invented the term in its modern sense, and with it we find
ourselves at the great source of modern intellectual life. The
comprehensiveness and subtlety of his analysis of the phenomenon left
nothing new to be said about it, and the Right and the Left forever after
accepted his description of modern man as simply true, while the Center
was impressed, intimidated, and put on the defensive by it. So persuasive
was Rousseau that he destroyed the self-confidence of the Enlightenment at
the moment of its triumph.
"It must not be forgotten that Rousseau begins his critique from
fundamental agreements with Locke, whom he greatly admired, about the
animal man. Man is by nature a solitary being, concerned only with his
preservation and his comfort. Rousseau, moreover, agrees that man makes
civil society by contract, for the sake of his preservation. He disagrees
with Locke that self-interest, however understood, is in any automatic
harmony with what civil society needs and demands. If Rousseau is right,
man's reason, calculating his best interest, will not lead him to wish to
be a good citizen, a law-abiding citizen. He will either be himself, or he
will be a citizen, or he will try to be both and be neither. In other
words, enlightenment is not enough to establish society, and even tends to
dissolve it.
"The road from the state of nature was very long, and nature is distant
from us now. A self-sufficient, solitary being must have undergone many
changes to become a needy, social one. On the way, the goal of happiness
was exchanged for the pursuit of safety and comfort, the means of
achieving happiness. Civil society is surely superior to a condition of
scarcity and universal war. All this artifice, however, preserves a being
who no longer knows what he is, who is so absorbed with existing that he
has forgotten his reason for existing, who in the event of actually
attaining full security and perfect comfort has no notion of what to do.
Progress culminates in the recognition that life is meaningfulness. Hobbes
was surely right to look for the most powerful sentiments in man, those
that exist independently of opinion and are always a part of man. But fear
of death, however powerful it may be and however useful it may be as a
motive for seeking peace and, hence, law with teeth in it, cannot be the
fundamental experience. It presupposes an even more fundamental one: that
life is good. The deepest experience is the pleasant sentiment of
existence. The idle, savage man can enjoy that sentiment. The busy
bourgeois cannot, with his hard work and his concern with dealing with
others rather than being himself.
"Nature still has something of the greatest importance to tell us. We may
be laboring to master it, but the reason for mastering nature comes from
nature. The fear of death on which Hobbes relied, and which is also
decisive for Locke, insists on the negative experience of nature and
obliterates the positive experience presupposed by it. This positive
experience is somehow still active in us; we are full of vague
dissatisfactions in our forgetfulness, but our minds must make an enormous
effort to find the natural sweetness of life in its fullness. The way back
is at least as long as the one that brought us here. For Hobbes and Locke
nature is near and unattractive, and man's movement into society was easy
and unambiguously good. For Rousseau nature is distant and attractive, and
the movement was hard and divided man. Just when nature seemed to have
been finally cast out or overcome in us, Rousseau gave birth to an
overwhelming longing for it in us. Our lost wholeness is there. One is
reminded of Plato's Symposium, but there the longing for wholeness was
directed toward knowledge of the ideas, of the ends. In Rousseau longing
is, in its initial expression, for the enjoyment of the primitive
feelings, found at the origins in the state of nature. Plato would have
united with Rousseau against the bourgeois in his insistence on the
essential humanness of longing for the good, as opposed to careful
avoidance of the bad. Neither longing nor enthusiasm belongs to the
bourgeois. The story of philosophy and the arts under Rousseau's influence
has been the search for, or fabrication of, plausible objects of longing
to counter bourgeois well-being and self-satisfaction. Part of that story
has been the bourgeois' effort to acquire the culture of longing as part
of its self-satisfaction.
"The opposition between nature and society is Rousseau's interpretation of
the cause of the dividedness of man. He finds that the bourgeois
experiences this dividedness in conflict between self-love and
love-of-others, inclination and duty, sincerity and hypocrisy, being
oneself and being alienated. This opposition between nature and society
pervades all modern discussion of the human problem. Hobbes and Locke made
the distinction in order to overcome all the tensions caused in man by the
demands of virtue, and then to make wholeness easy for him. They thought
that they had reduced the distance between inclination and duty by
deriving all duty from inclination; Rousseau argued that, if anything,
they had increased that distance. He thus restored the older, pre-modern
sense of the dividedness of man and hence of the complexity of his
attainment of happiness, the pursuit of which liberal society guarantees
him while making its attainment impossible. But the restoration takes
place on very different grounds, as can be seen in the fact that in the
past men traced the tension to the irreconcilable demands of body and
soul, not of nature and society. This too opens up a rich field for
reflection on Rousseau's originality. The blame shifts, and the focus of
the perennial quest for unity is altered. Man was born whole, and it is at
least conceivable that he become whole once again. Hope and despair of a
kind not permitted by the body-soul distinction arise. What one is to
think of oneself and one's desires changes. The correctives range from
revolution to therapy, but there is little place for the confessional or
for mortification of the flesh. Rousseau's Confessions were, in opposition
to those of Augustine, intended to show that he was born good, that the
body's desires are good, that there is no original sin. Man's nature has
been maimed by a long history; and now he must live in society, for which
he is not suited and which makes impossible demands on him. There is
either an uneasy acquiescence to the present or the attempt in one way or
another to return to the past, or the search for a creative synthesis of
the two poles, nature and society." The Closing of the American Mind,
Allan Bloom, Simon & Schuster, 1987, pps. 167-170 (and from Emile,
Rousseau, pp. 39-40, ed. Bloom, Basic Books, 1979).
Describing Kant’s view in Critique of Judgment (his 3rd Critique):
“According to the principle of ‘intrinsic finality,’ ‘an organized natural
product is one in which every part is reciprocally both end and means.”
Taylor, Mark C. The Moment of Complexity: Emerging Network Culture.
University of Chicago. 2001. p. 85. Quotes are to Kant, Immanuel. Critique
of Judgment, translated by James Meredith. Oxford University Press. p. 22.
“Modernity harbored the ideas of individual emancipation, the generalized
secularization of values, and the distinction between the true, the
beautiful, and the good. However, individualism henceforth no longer only
meant autonomy and emancipation but also atomization and anonymization.
Secularization meant not only liberation from religious dogmas but also
loss of foundations, anxiety, doubt, and nostalgia for the great
certitudes. The distinctiveness of values led not only to moral autonomy,
aesthetic exaltation, and the free search for truth but also to
demoralization, frivolous estheticism, and nihilism. The erstwhile
rejuvenating virtue of the idea of the new (new = better = necessary =
progress) was exhausting itself and was typically reserved for detergents,
television screens, and automobile performance.” Morin, Edgar. Homeland
Earth: A Manifesto for a New Millennium. 1999. Hampton Press. p. 58.
“To begin with, we could say that reality is that which is immediate. Yet
this immediacy itself refers to two different realities: the one temporal,
the other factual.
“The first has to do with the reality of the present. This reality is
quite strong and has abolished a part of yesterday’s reality, but it is
also very weak, as it will itself be partially abolished by the reality of
tomorrow.”
“...The factual meaning of the term reality refers to situations, facts,
and events that are visible in the present. Yet perceptible facts and
events often hide facts or events that go unperceived and can even hide a
still invisible reality.” Morin, Edgar. Homeland Earth: A Manifesto for a
New Millennium. 1999. Hampton Press. p. 99-100.
"Again, we have watched with interest Jung developing his concept of a
'collective unconscious' of humanity as a whole, a concept which is
inherently repugnant to the foundation of idolatry on which he had to
build it. Yet, because of that very idolatry, the traditional myths and
the archetypes which he tells us are the representations of the collective
unconscious, are assumed by him to be, and always to have been neatly
insulated from the world of nature with which, according to their own
account, they were mingled or united.
"The psychological interpretation of mythology is, it is true, a long way
nearer to an understanding of participation than the old 'personified
causes' of Tylor and Frazer and Lempriere's Classical Dictionary. But it
is still a long way off. In the last resort, when it actually comes up
against the nature-content of the myths, it still relies on the old
anthropological assumption of 'projection'. I believe it will seem very
strange to the historian of the future, that a literal-minded generation
began to accept the actuality of a 'collective unconscious' before it
could even admit the possibility of a 'collective conscious--in the shape
of the phenomenal world." Barfield, Owen, Saving the Appearances: A Study
of Idolatry, Harcourt Brace, pps. 134-5.
"How far one will carry a set of categories into detail is a more arbitray
matter here [contextualism] than in any other relatively adequate world
theory. In other theories one can pretty clearly distinguish categories
(the basic univesal structural features of nature) from subcategoreies,
which are clearly derivative from the former and lead down into the minor
detailed structures of limited portions of nature. There is an orderliness
about such theories. Even formism has it, dispersive as it is in
categorial structure. But, so to speak, disorder is a categorial feature
of contextualism, and so radically so that it must not even exclude order.
That is, the categories must be so framed as not to exclude from the world
any degree of order it may be found to have, nor to deny that this order
may have come out of disorder and may return into disorder again--order
being defined in any way you please, so long as it does not deny the
possibility of disorder or another order in nature also. This italicized
restriction is the forcible one in contextualism, and amounts to the
assertion that change is categorial and not derivative in any degree at
all.
"Change in this radical sense is denied by all other world theories. If
such radical change is not a feature of the world, if there are
unchangeable structures in nature like the forms of formism or the
space-time structure of mechanism, then contextualism is false.
Contextualism is constantly threatened with evidences for permanent
structures in nature. It is constantly on the verge of falling back upon
underlying mechanistic structures, or of resolving into the overarching
implicit integrations of organicism. Its recourse in these emergencies is
always to hurry back to the given event, and to emphasize the change and
novelty that is immediately felt there, so that sometimes it seems to be
headed for an utter skepticism. But it avoids this impasse by vigorously
asserting the reality of the structure of the given event, the historic
event as it actually goes on. The whole universe, it asserts, is such as
this event is, whatever this is." Pepper, Stephen C., World Hypotheses,
University of California, 1942 & 1970, pp. 234-5.
"Whereas in formism and mechanism it is taken for granted that any object
or event can be completely analyzed into its constituents, no such
assumption is made in contextualism. According to contextualism only
events exist and since they are totally interwoven with their context
(which includes the observer), they cannot be completely analyzed. Hence
one cannot get to the bottom of things. The world is bottomless and there
is no ultimate nature of things because there is no-thing. There is only
oneness. Since in this oneness every so-called event is interconnected
with the whole cosmos, 'blowing your nose is just as cosmic and ultimate
as Newton's writing down his gravitational formula. The fact that his
formula is much more useful to many people does not make it any more
real'.
"The implications of contextualism for the question 'what is life?' are
far-reaching. Probably the question would be considered inadequate because
it is too abstract and does not arise out of concrete events in their
contexts. Living organisms must be understood in their context which is
their environment, which includes other organisms as well as so-called
abiotic components.
"Since in contextualism change is fundamental we should use verbs instead
of nouns to indicate more appropriately the acting and changing. Thus the
noun 'life' is better replaced by the verb 'to live' or its gerund
'living,' which refer to an activity that occurs always in concrete
situations immensely rich, complex and fluid.
"Operation(al)ism, which can be assimilated to contextualism, also
emphasizes activity in terms of operations. Meaning cannot be found in
static abstraction as, for example, in formism, but must be expressed in
terms of concrete operations." Sattler, Rolf. Bio-Philosophy.
Springer Verla. 1986. Pp. 245-6.
"About fifty years of work in which thousands of clever men have had their
share have, in fact, produced a rich crop of several hundred heuristic
concepts, but, alas, scarcely a single principle worthy of a place in the
list of fundamentals.
"It is all too clear that the vast majority of the concepts of
contemporary psychology, psychiatry, anthropology, sociology, and
economics are totally detached from the network of scientific
fundamentals....
"No man, after all, has ever seen or experienced formless and unsorted
matter; just as no man has ever seen or experienced a 'random' event....
"...my critical comments above about the metaphoric use of 'energy' in the
behavioral sciences add up to a rather simple accusation of many of my
colleagues, that they have tried to build the bridge to the wrong half of
the ancient dichotomy between form and substance. The conservative laws
for energy and matter concern substance rather than form. But mental
process, ideas, communication, organization, differentiation, pattern, and
so on, are matters of form rather than substance." Bateson, Gregory, Steps
to an Ecology of Mind, Ballantine, 1972, p. xix, xxv.
"Kant's penetrating critique had effectively pulled the rug out from under
the human mind's pretensions to certain knowledge of things in themselves,
eliminating in principle any human cognition of the ground of the
world....
"From Hume and Kant through Darwin, Marx, Freud and beyond, an unsettling
conclusion was becoming inescapable: Human thought was determined,
structured, and very probably distorted by a multitude of overlapping
factors--innate but nonabsolute mental categories, habit, history,
culture, social class, biology, language, imagination, emotion, the
personal unconscious, the collective unconscious. In the end, the human
mind could not be relied upon as an accurate judge of reality. The
original Cartesian certainty, that which served as foundation for the
modern confidence in human reason, was no longer defensible.
"Henceforth, philosophy concerned itself largely with the clarification of
epistemological problems, with the analysis of language, with the
philosophy of science, or with phenomenological and existentialist
analyses of human experience. Despite the incongruence of aims and
pre-dispositions among the various schools of twentieth-century
philosophy, there was general agreement on one crucial point: the
impossibility of apprehending an objective cosmic order with the human
intelligence." Tarnas, Richard, The Passion of the Western Mind, Harmony,
New York, 1991, pp. 340-353.
"Kant had offered his definition [of enlightenment] in an essay that
addressed the question 'What is enlightenment?' It was first published in
1784, three years after the first edition of his Critique of Pure Reason
had appeared. 'Enlightenment is man's exit from his self-incurred
tutelage,' Kant had written. 'Tutelage is man's inability to make use of
his understanding without direction from another. Self-incurred is this
tutelage when its cause lies not in lack of reason but in lack of
resolution and courage to use it without direction from another. Sapere
aude! [Dare to know!] 'Have courage to use your own reason'--that is the
motto of enlightenment.'
"As Foucault reads this definition--which he tacitly endorses as a fitting
description of his lifework--the emphasis falls on courage, as the
specific virtue of the 'will to know'; and, above all, on the admonition
'to use your own reason,' a stress that, in effect transforms Kant's
injunction into a precursor of Nietzsche's injunction, to discover 'the
meaning of your own life.'
"After Kant, it is indeed Nietzsche who perhaps came closest to describing
'the problem of enlightenment' as Foucault himself understood it.
Philosophers, Nietzsche had written some one hundred years after Kant's
essay, 'must no longer accept concepts as a gift, nor merely purify and
polish them, but first make and create them, present them and make them
convincing. Hitherto one has generally trusted one's concepts as if they
were a wonderful dowry from some sort of wonderland.' But this trust must
be replaced by mistrust. 'What is needed above all'--and this is where the
Nietzschean 'will to know' finds its true vocation--is an absolute
skepticism toward all concepts.' Hence 'critique.'" Miller, James, The
Passion of Michel Foucault, Simon & Schuster, 1993, pp. 302-3.
"Philosophy is the attempt to be at home everywhere in the universe."
Corvalis, Romantic poet
"Difference, being of the nature of relationship, is not located in time
or in space. We say that the white spot is 'there,' 'in the middle of the
blackboard,' but the difference between the spot and the blackboard is not
'there.' It is not in the spot; it is not in the blackboard; it is not in
the space between the board and the chalk. I could perhaps lift the chalk
off the board and send it to Australia, but the difference would not be
destroyed or even shifted because difference does not have location.
"When I wipe the blackboard, where does the difference go? In one sense,
the difference is randomized and irreversibly gone, as 'I' shall be gone
when I die. In another sense, the difference will endure as an idea--as
part of my karma--as long as this book is read, perhaps as long as the
ideas in this book go on to form other ideas, reincorporated into other
minds. But this enduring karmic information will be information about an
imaginary spot on an imaginary blackboard.
"Kant argued long ago that this piece of chalk contains a million
potential facts (Tatsachen) but that only a very few of these become truly
facts by affecting the behavior of entities capable of responding to
facts. For Kant's Tatsachen, I would substitute differences and point out
that the number of potential differences in this chalk is infinite but
that very few of them become effective differences (i.e., items of
information) in the mental process of any larger entity. Information
consists of differences that make a difference....
"If there are readers who still want to equate information and difference
with energy, I would remind them that zero differs from one and can
therefore trigger response. The starving amoeba will become more active,
hunting for food; the growing plant will bend away from the dark, and the
income tax people will become alerted by the declarations which you did
not send. Events which are not are different from those which might have
been, and events which are not surely contribute no energy." Bateson,
Gregory, Mind and Nature; a Necessary Unity, Bantom, 1980, pp. 109-111.
"When we come to contextualism, we pass from an analytical into a
synthetic type of theory. It is characteristic of the synthetic theories
that their root metaphors cannot satisfactorily be denoted even to a first
approximation by well-known common-sense concepts such as similarity, the
artifact, or the machine. We are too likely to be misunderstood at the
start, even though the basic synthetic concepts do originate in common
sense or are, at least, discoverable there. The best term out of common
sense to suggest the point of origin of conextualism is probably the
historic event. And this we shall accordingly call the root metaphor of
this theory.
"By historic event, however, the contextualist does not mean primarily a
past event, one that is, so to speak, dead and has to be exhumed. He means
the event alive in its present. What we ordinarily mean by history, he
says, is an attempt to re-present events, to make them in some way alive
again. The real historic event, the event in its actuality, is what it is
going on now, the dynamic dramatic active event. We may call it an 'act,'
if we like, and if we take care of our use of the term. But it is not an
act conceived as alone or cut off that we mean; it is an act in and with
its setting, an act in its context.
"To give instances of this root metaphor in our language with the minimum
risk of misunderstanding, we should use only verbs. It is doing, and
enduring, and enjoying: making a boat, running a race, laughing at a joke,
persuading an assembly, unraveling a mystery, solving a problem, removing
an obstacle, exploring a country, communicating with a friend, creating a
poem, re-creating a poem. These acts or events are all intrinsically
complex, composed of interconnected activities with continuously changing
patterns. They are like incidents in the plot of a novel or drama. They
are literally the incidents of life. The contextualist finds that
everything in the world consists of such incidents. When we catch the
idea, it seems very obvious. For this reason, it is sometimes easy to
confuse the historic event of contextualism with common-sense fact, and
some contextualists have encouraged the confusion. But there are lots of
things in common sense that are not events. Common sense is full of
animistic, formistic, and mechanistic substances. But contextualism holds
tight to the changing present event. This event itself, once we note it,
is obvious enough, but the tightness of the contextualists' hold upon it
is not usual. It is this hold that makes contextualism a distinctive
philosophic attitude and a world theory. World Hypotheses, Stephen C.
Pepper, University of California, 1942 & 1970, pp. 232-3.
“Before long the problem of human action which is the concern of tragedy
was to become a matter for intellectual cognition; Socrates insists on
solving the problem through knowledge of the good. That is the ultimate
abstraction of the real, its transformation into a teleological concept.
Where a divine world had endowed the human world with meaning, we now find
the universal determining the particular.” Snell, Bruno. The Discovery of
the Mind in Greek Philosophy and Literature, p. 112.
“What we see around ourselves in recent decades has been an enormous
expansion of cultural production. There are over 1 million publications
annually in the natural sciences, over 100,000 in the social sciences, and
comparable numbers n the humanities (Price, 1986: 266). To perceive the
world as a text is not too inaccurate a description, perhaps not of the
world itself, but of the life position of intellectuals: we are almost
literally buried in papers. As the raw size of intellectual production
goes up, the reward to the average individual goes down–at least the pure
intellectual rewards of being recognized for one’s ideas and of seeing
their impact on others. The pessimism and self-doubt of the intellectual
community under these circumstances is not surprising.
“Which of the three types of stagnation do we exemplify? Loss of cultural
capital (Stagnation A), certainly, marked by the inability of today’s
intellectuals to build constructively on the achievements of their
predecessors. Simultaneously there exists a cult of the classics
(Stagnation B): the historicism and footnote scholarship of our times, in
which doing intellectual history becomes superior to creating it. And also
we have the stagnation (C) of technical refinement: to take just a few
instances, the acute refinements and formalisms of logical and linguistic
philosophy have proceeded apace in little specialized niches; in the same
way among all factions of the intellectual world today we find the
prevalence of esoterica, of subtleties, and of impenetrable in-group
vocabularies.” Collins, Randall. The Sociology of Philosophies: A Global
Theory of Intellectual Change. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
1999. p. 521.
“Modern philosophy, in stressing the illusory nature of sensory
appearances, has congratulated itself on having fulfilled its duty to be
suspicious by distinguishing between primary and secondary qualities while
accepting unquestioningly the deeper illusion: the notion of instantaneous
bits of matter simply located in space.” Griffin, David Ray. Unsnarling
the World-Knot: Consciousness, Freedom, and the Mind-Body Problem.
University of California Press. 1998. p. 120.
“Before the notion of articulation, it was impossible to answer no to the
question ‘Did the ferments (or the microbes) exist before Pasteur’ without
falling into some sort of idealism. The subject-object dichotomy
distributed activity and passivity in such a way that whatever was taken
by one was lost to the other. If Pasteur makes up the microbes, that is,
invents them, then the microbes are passive. If the microbes ‘lead Pasteur
in his thinking’ then it is he who is the passive observer of their
activity. We have begun to understand, however, that the pair
human-nonhuman does not involve a tug-of-war between two opposite forces.
On the contrary, the more activity there is from one, the more activity
there is from the other. The more Pasteur works in his laboratory, the
more autonomous his ferment becomes. Idealism was the impossible effort to
give activity back to the humans, without dismantling the Yalta pact which
had made activity a zero-sum game–and without redefining the very notion
of action, as we will see in Chapter 9. In all its various forms–including
of course social constructivism–idealism had a nice polemical virtue
against those who granted too much independence to the empirical world.
But polemics are fun to watch for only so long. If we cease to treat
activity as a rare commodity of which only one team can have possession,
it stops being fun to watch people trying to deprive one another of what
all the players could have aplenty.” Latour, Bruno. Pandora’s Hope: Essays
on the Reality of Science Studies. Harvard University Press. 1999. p. 147.
“Nonhumans stabilize social negotiations. Nonhumans are at once pliable
and durable: they can be shaped very quickly but once shaped, last far
longer than the interactions that fabricated them. Latour, Bruno.
Pandora’s Hope: Essays on the Reality of Science Studies. Harvard
University Press. 1999. p. 210.
“Because it believes in the total separation of humans and nonhumans, and
because it simultaneously cancels out this separation, the Constitution
has made the moderns invincible. If you criticize them by saying that
Nature is a world constructed by human hands, they will show you that it
is transcendent, that science is a mere intermediary allowing access to
Nature, and that they keep their hands off. If you tell them that we are
free and that our destiny is in our own hands, they will tell you that
Society is transcendent and its laws infinitely surpass us. If you object
that they are being duplicitous, they will show you that they never
confuse the Laws of Nature with imprescriptible human freedom. If you
believe them and direct your attention elsewhere, they will take advantage
of this to transfer thousands of objects from Nature into the social body
while procuring for this body the solidity of natural things. If you turn
round suddenly, as in the children’s game ‘Mother, may I?’, they will
freeze, looking innocent, as if they hadn’t budged; here, on the left, are
things themselves; there, on the right, is the free society of speaking,
thinking subjects, values and of signs. Everything happens in the middle,
everything passes between the two, everything happens by way of mediation,
translation and networks, but this space does not exist, it has no place.”
Latour, Bruno. We Have Never Been Modern. Harvard University Press. 1993.
p. 37.
“Native Americans were not mistaken when they accused the Whites of having
forked tongues. By separating the relations of political power from the
relations of scientific reasoning while continuing to shore up power with
reason and reason with power, the moderns have always had two irons in the
fire. They have become invincible.”
“You think that thunder is a divinity. The modern critique will show that
it is generated by mere physical mechanisms that have no influence over
the progress of human affairs. You are stuck in a traditional economy? The
modern critique will show you that physical mechanisms can upset the
progress of human affairs by mobilizing huge productive forces. You think
that the spirits of the ancestors hold you forever hostage to their laws?
The modern critique will show you that you are hostage to yourselves and
that the spiritual world is your own human - too human - construction. You
then think that you can do everything and develop your societies as you
see fit? The modern critique will show you that the iron laws of society
and economics are much more inflexible than those of your ancestors. You
are indignant that the world is being mechanized? The modern critique will
tell you about the creator God to whom everything belongs and who gave man
everything. You are indignant that society is secular? The modern critique
will show you that spirituality is thereby liberated, and that a wholly
spiritual religion is far superior. You call yourself religious? The
modern critique will have a hearty laugh at your expense!” Latour, Bruno.
We Have Never Been Modern. Harvard University Press. 1993. p. 38.
“It seems to me that only in the seventeenth century did both trends
converge into one world picture: namely, the Nominalists’ passion for
unequivocation with the Renaissance sense of the homogeneity of nature–one
nature with forces to replace the many Aristotelian static natures.”
Funkenstein, Amos. Theology and the Scientific Imagination From the Middle
Ages to the Seventeenth Century. Princeton University Press. 1986. p. 72.
“Only ‘the idealized experiment shows the clew which really forms the
foundation of the mechanics of motion–namely that bodies would continue
moving forever if not hindered by external obstacles. This discovery
taught us that intuitive confusions based on immediate observation are not
always to be trusted.’” Einstein and Infeld. The Evolution of Physics, pp.
6-9; quoted in: Funkenstein, Amos. Theology and the Scientific Imagination
From the Middle Ages to the Seventeenth Century. Princeton University
Press. 1986. p. 153.
“Alternative worlds are, in Aristotle’s eyes, strictly disjunctive; and
since ours exists, they do not. Our universe is unique, and nothing in it
could profitably be taken out of its context and examined under ideal,
non-existence conditions. These are the deeper reasons why Aristotle was
not willing, as Clauberg rightly observed, to see things ‘as they are in
themselves’ but always insisted that we should see them ‘as they are in
respect to each other.’” Funkenstein, Amos. Theology and the Scientific
Imagination From the Middle Ages to the Seventeenth Century. Princeton
University Press. 1986. p. 163-4.
“Galileo, as Blumenberg rightly emphasized, does not compare an ‘ideal’
state to a ‘deficient’ reality; the very deviation of the real from the
ideal can be measured and explained with an ever more complicated model.
Rather than comparing reality to the ideal, he compares the complex to the
simple. The scientific revolution of the seventeenth century learned to
assert the impossible as a limiting case of reality.” Funkenstein, Amos.
Theology and the Scientific Imagination From the Middle Ages to the
Seventeenth Century. Princeton University Press. 1986. p. 177-78.
“The study of nature in the seventeenth century was neither predominantly
idealistic nor empirical. It was first and foremost constructive,
pragmatic in the radical sense. It would lead to the conviction that only
the doable–at least in principle–is also understandable: verum et factum
convertuntur. Funkenstein, Amos. Theology and the Scientific Imagination
From the Middle Ages to the Seventeenth Century. Princeton University
Press. 1986. p. 177.
“Together with the ideal of absolute rigor, the seventeenth century also
gave up the ideal of absolute exactness of measurement–only in such a way,
as Anneliese Maier observed, were the exact sciences made possible.”
Funkenstein, Amos. Theology and the Scientific Imagination From the Middle
Ages to the Seventeenth Century. Princeton University Press. 1986. p. 313
(because science freed itself from the mathematics of perfect
forms–circles, etc. to let natural things dictate the math including much
inexactness of measure)
“The seventeenth century did not abandon the notion of perfection, or
harmony, of the cosmos; it replaced the geometric-statical symmetry of the
Platonic and Peripatetic tradition with a notion of dynamic consonance.
With the growing insight into the symbolic-formal character of
mathematics, ‘simplicity’ came to mean generality rather than absolute
symmetry.” Funkenstein, Amos. Theology and the Scientific Imagination From
the Middle Ages to the Seventeenth Century. Princeton University Press.
1986. p. 313-4
“It may appear ironic that the medieval, elitist image of knowledge was
coupled with Aristotelian philosophy–basically a common-sense philosophy
that aims to explicate ‘what everyone knows, only better’; while the new,
egalitarian image of an open, systematic knowledge was coupled with
sciences that in part were now derived from counter-intuitive premises and
soon proliferated and became so technical that they could hardly be
mastered by the educated layperson. The tension was not as pronounced in
the seventeenth century as it became in the eighteenth; and it found
temporary relief in the slowly emerging image of a common ‘culture’ or
‘education.’ A new entity, ‘culture,’ connoted more than ‘mores’ and less
than ‘learning.’” Funkenstein, Amos. Theology and the Scientific
Imagination From the Middle Ages to the Seventeenth Century. Princeton
University Press. 1986. p. 359
“Perhaps one might say that the theocentric theologies of the Middle Ages
gave way to cosmocentric theologies in the seventeenth century, which
again were superseded by a variety of anthropocentric theologies down to
our century.” Funkenstein, Amos. Theology and the Scientific Imagination
From the Middle Ages to the Seventeenth Century. Princeton University
Press. 1986. p. 360
"What is it, finally, that we hope for? A way of seeing things that would
value each individual, recognize each individual's unique contributions,
empower each individual--ending the psychological circle of hierarchy and
competition. A new social contract not only with each other but also with
the planet and the other creatures who share the earth.
"This alternative system, with its new spirit and aura, is still in the
process of formation. Like a star, twinkling with light and motion, it is
radiating out waves of energy to all around it, particles of light and
illumination. This is the third step of the process that has been building
for so long, and one that will continue far into the future. Hite, Shere,
The Hite Report; Women and Love; A Cultural Revolution in Progress, Alfred
A. Knopf, 1987, p. 765.
“Ockham’s emphasis on unequivocal terminology was even stronger than that
of Duns Scotus. Only discrete entities, singulars, exist and they do not
need the mediation of universals either for their existence or for their
immediate, ‘intuitive’ cognition.” Funkenstein, Amos. Theology and the
Scientific Imagination From the Middle Ages to the Seventeenth Century.
Princeton University Press. 1986. p. 27.
“In sum, disembodied consciousness, a social position of domination, and
the very production of idealist thought and philosophy strictly converge.”
Brown, Wendy. Politics Out of History. Princeton University Press. 2001.
P. 82.
“The aggression and paralysis entailed in conviction, its urgency and
anxiety, remind us again that enlightenment is always bounded by
encroaching dark, that in modernity truth has never really been fully
convinced of itself.” Brown, Wendy. Politics Out of History. Princeton
University Press. 2001. P. 93.
"The division of labour has endowed cognition with autonomy; autonomous
cognition has engendered a nature within which no activity can be
autonomous. That is the problem." Gellner, Ernest. Plough, Sword and Book:
The Structure of Human History. University of Chicago Press. 1988. p. 136.
“...Putnam’s semantic externalism may be variously summarized. Negatively
described, it says that the notion of meaning is not ambiguous between
intension and extension; that individual psychological states do not
determine extensions; that an individual in isolation cannot in principle
grasp any arbitrary concept whatsoever; that an individual’s grasp of his
or her concepts does not totally determine the extension of all the
individual’s terms; that knowledge of meanings is not private property;
and – perhaps most radically – that meanings are best not conceived as
entity- or object-like at all. Positively described, the position has
three central strands. First, our notion of meaning is object- or
reality-involving in the sense that, at least in central cases, it is
significantly determined by reference rather than vice versa; second, much
concept-possession, and much grasp of meaning is essentially social in
character; third, our individuation of meanings, concepts, beliefs, and
what they are true of are and ought to be settled in multifarious ways, by
a range of culture- and environment-involving factors, including the
purposes and context(s) of a speaker’s assertion, her causal links with
the objects, the use of stereotypes within a community to generate
linguistic obligation, the linguistic division of labor, and ultimately
judgments as to reasonableness and charity available to speakers in virtue
of their ‘agent-centered’ self-conceptions as participants in a variety of
practices.” Floyd, Juliet. 2005. “Putnam’s ‘The Meaning of ‘’Meaning’‘:
Externalism in Historical Context.” Pps. 17-52. Ben-Menahem, Yemima, ed.
Hilary Putnam. Cambridge University Press. P. 18.
“I shall say that entities may have intrinsic quiddity without intrinsic
haecceity. Electrons possess such a quiddity – an electron is not a
proton, or a logarithm or anything else – but there is no way intrinsic to
electrons to single one out from all others; so it lacks haecceity.”
Stachel, John. 2005. “Structural Realism and Contextual Individuality.”
Pps. 203-219. Hilary Putnam. Edited by Yemima Ben-Menahem. Cambridge
University Press. P. 204.
“Reading this chain [from field quanta to galaxies and super-clusters]
from the top down, one is struck by the loss of individuality as we
proceed downward. In Bernal’s biological examples, one organism is
certainly distinct from another, even if both are of the same species; and
this feature of distinctive individuality persists all the way down to the
macromolecules containing an organism’s genetic code. But in our physical
chain, while one star is certainly distinct from another, by the point at
which we get down to the atoms – let alone the nuclei and electrons of
which an atom is composed – this feature of distinctive individuality (haecceity)
has been lost.”
“Conversely, if we read the physical chain from the bottom up, the
striking thing is the emergence, first of indistinguishable units – field
quanta – from the quantum fields; then the organization of these units
into still indistinguishable complexes, but all possessing quiddity; and,
only further up the chain, the emergence of complex units with a
distinctive individuality.” Stachel, John. 2005. “Structural Realism and
Contextual Individuality.” Pps. 203-219. Hilary Putnam. Edited by Yemima
Ben-Menahem. Cambridge University Press. P. 209.
“Putnam’s current position can then be seen, in his own words, as the
attempt ‘to recover our ordinary notion of representation (and of a world
to be represented)’ without committing the ‘philosophical error of
supposing that the term reality must refer to a single superthing.’”
Mueller, Axel & Arthur Fine. 2005. “Realism, Beyond Miracles.” Pps.
83-124. From Ben-Menahem, Yemima, Editor. Hilary Putnam. Cambridge
University Press. P. 84. Subquotes are from Putnam, Hilary. 1994. Words
and Life. Harvard University Press and from 1999. The Threefold Chord:
Mind, Body, and World. Columbia University Press respectively.
“What is required for ‘sharing’ a situation and considering it as shared
is the elaboration of an overlap in respective partial extensions (of the
respective correlated concept-signs) as applied to the environment (as
parsed by each version into their relevant parameters). It does not rely
on shared descriptions. Since the partial extensions are accessible, in
ordinary inductive ways, to the users of either description, there is also
no supposition of direct access. Finally, since in case the correlated
descriptions disagree this can produce a revision of one of the
descriptions by way of the other, Putnam’s view requires no
incorrigibility. Thus access to a situation as shared is not through
neutrality or direct intuition, but through common inductive practices
involving communication and cooperation. To this effect, Putnam cites
Dewey by saying that ‘the whole interaction is cognitive.’” Mueller, Axel
& Arthur Fine. 2005. “Realism, Beyond Miracles.” Pps. 83-124. From Ben-Menahem,
Yemima, Editor. Hilary Putnam. Cambridge University Press. P. 114.
“... our practices of making empirical claims and taking them to be
objectively correct descriptions of a publicly accessible environment do
not presuppose any such superthing (a uniquely structured realm of
underlying reality). Each claim does presuppose a variously accessible,
richly conceptualized and sometimes multiply organizable local environment
for its evaluation, an environment that, for all these reasons, can be
common to many differently predisposed human beings.” Mueller, Axel &
Arthur Fine. 2005. “Realism, Beyond Miracles.” Pps. 83-124. From Ben-Menahem,
Yemima, Editor. Hilary Putnam. Cambridge University Press. Pps. 117-8.
“He [Mill] acknowledge that people often make a distinction between a
cause, which supposedly takes an active role in bringing the event about,
and the conditions, which supposedly take a somehow humbler role in the
whole process. But Mill argued that this distinction was spurious: ‘The
real cause is the whole of these antecedents; and we have, philosophically
speaking, no right to give the name of cause to one of them exclusively of
the others.’ Rockwell, W. Teed. Neither Brain nor Ghost: A Nondualist
Alternative to the Mind-Brain Identity Theory. 2005. MIT Press. P. 51.
Subquote is from J.S. Mill. 1851. A System of Logic, Rationcinative and
Inductive. vol. 1. John W. Parker. P. 214.
“They [Ernst Nagel and Bertrand Russell] argued that causality was a
commonsense concept that had to be radically revised, and sometimes even
dispensed with, for us to be truly scientific. But the revisions they
proposed left no room for the concept of intrinsic causal powers. For
there to be such powers, there must be some sense in which the cause has
power over its effect and is distinct from it. Supposedly, the cause
resides in the object, and the effect is the impact that the cause has on
the outside world. But if the cause and the effect are equally dependent
on each other, we have a causal network, rather than a community of
autonomous objects with intrinsic causal powers.” Rockwell, W. Teed. 2005.
Neither Brain nor Ghost: A Nondualist Alternative to the Mind-Brain
Identity Theory. MIT Press. P. 62.
“Chairs are chairs, just as hearts are hearts, because there is a network
of relationships in the real world that makes them that way. Certain
entities are constituted by relationships that do not obviously refer to
or presuppose the existence of human beings. But even such entities as the
chemical elements presuppose certain relationships to laboratory
procedures and measurements. It would make no sense to say that this
substance is still sulfur, even though it does not behave the way sulfur
would behave in the laboratory.” Rockwell, W. Teed. 2005. Neither Brain
nor Ghost: A Nondualist Alternative to the Mind-Brain Identity Theory. MIT
Press. P. 143.
“The vocabulary
reveals our assumptions. Subjects are treated as radically separable from
objects. Design, or form, originates either inside or outside the
subject-agent. A strict distinction is made between active creation and
passive imitation, between originating a design and serving as a conduit
through which it passes.
“But we are not committed to these assumptions in order to consider nature
and design. We can admit our interactive role in the definition of
problems, in the choice and conceptualization of model, in the mode of
investigation, in the construction of knowledge itself. I would even
playfully suggest that we should increase the ambiguity of design by
including imitation or study, or even perception, in the semantic complex
that already embraces the creation of a design, the design created, and
the design that guides our work.” Oyama, Susan. 2000. Evolution’s Eye: A
Systems View of the Biology-Culture Divide. Duke University Press. P. 144.
“Two incidents prompted my own thinking about these issues. One was a
comment by Mary Catherine Bateson about the much-used metaphor of the
earth as mother. She offered some alternatives – the earth and ourselves
as co-parents, for example, or the earth as child – and made the gentle
suggestion that we needn’t insist on only one.” Oyama, Susan. 2000.
Evolution’s Eye: A Systems View of the Biology-Culture Divide. Duke
University Press. P. 145.
“Science’s ability to predict and control (the twin goals of contemporary
science – whatever happened to the ability to understand?) often seems
inadequate to the cascade of unintended consequences that frequently
follows technological advance. These two, excessive power and inadequate
power, are not contradictory. Both are aspects of our embeddedness in the
world, an embeddedness denied by conventional accounts of objective
scientific knowledge.” Oyama, Susan. 2000. Evolution’s Eye: A Systems View
of the Biology-Culture Divide. Duke University Press. P. 151.
“Biology speaks of behavior in terms of the body, largely in the language
of causes, while nonscientists tend to use the language of mind and
reasons. It is psychologists’ uneasy task to mediate between these realms,
between the biological discourses of evolution, function, mechanism, and
physiology, and the political and ethical discourses of persons and acts.
Psychology serves, in short, as a sort of disciplinary pineal gland.
Building on a distinction between necessary nature and contingent nurture,
however, psychologists frequently oscillate between the two realms,
patching together an unintegrated combination of the biological and the
cultural, the physical and the mental, and, as we shall see, even the
determined and the free. Insofar as it is committed to being scientific,
which today often means being biological (and, increasingly, cognitivist,
in the sense of thinking in terms of information-processing mechanisms
modeled on computer technology), psychology affords less and less room for
human subjects. Indeed, part of the mission of modern science is the
replacement of mentalistic explanation with mechanistic accounts, of
intentions with causes.” Oyama, Susan. 2000. Evolution’s Eye: A Systems
View of the Biology-Culture Divide. Duke University Press. P. 167.
“To accentuate the irrelevance of the nature-nurture opposition to these
processes, I have suggested a recasting of the terms. Nature then refers
not to some static reality standing behind the changing characteristics of
the phenotype, but to the changing organism itself. It is plural in a
number of senses: Many ‘natures’ (organisms-in-transition) constitute a
species, rather than some single species essence, and an organism has as
many ‘natures’ as it has situational and developmental moments. Nurture
becomes a cover term for all interactions that produce, maintain, and
change natures. At the scale that interests most psychologists, it is
primarily people’s exchanges with each other and their surroundings that
are relevant.” Oyama, Susan. 2000. Evolution’s Eye: A Systems View of the
Biology-Culture Divide. Duke University Press. P. 181.
“Rather than contrasting autonomously acting persons with passive objects,
perhaps we can consider these to be two stances toward certain human
interactions. One is oriented more toward considerations and consequences
as seen from the agent’s point(s) of view and occurring in a social
context in which that agent is able to communicate acceptable, or at least
intelligible, reasons for acting. The other takes the point of view of
some (third-person) observer. Moral agency does not require freedom from
causes (what could this mean?) or even from biological causes. Rather, it
requires, precisely, embeddedness in a causal world. Only there can one be
subject to the joys, pains, desires, and perplexities that give rise to
action; only there can one affect the world; only there can one be engaged
by the exchanges that constitute human life; only there can one be moved
to encourage some outcomes and prevent others; and only there can one be
positioned among others who regard one as responsible. Such positions are
not foregone, however. The earlier discussion of homosexuality shows how
some people are attempting a strategic repositioning while others oppose
it. In Shotter’s ‘political economy of selfhood,’ people enhance and limit
each other’s opportunities for development.” Oyama, Susan. 2000.
Evolution’s Eye: A Systems View of the Biology-Culture Divide. Duke
University Press. P. 183. Subquote is from Shotter, John. Social
Accountability and Selfhood. Blackwell. 1984.
“Delight
in the Medieval Model is expressed by Dante or Jean de Meung rather than
by Albertus and Aquinas. Partly, no doubt, this is because expression of
whatever emotion, is not the business of philosophers. But I suspect this
is not the whole story. It is not in the nature of things that great
thinkers should take much interest in Models. They have more difficult and
more controversial matters in hand. Every Model is a construct of answered
questions. The expert is engaged either in raising new questions or in
giving new answers to old ones. When he is doing the first, the old,
agreed Model is of no interest to him; when he is doing the second, he is
beginning an operation which will finally destroy the old Model
altogether.
“One particular class of experts, the great spiritual writers, ignore the
Model almost completely. We need to know something about the Model if we
are to read Chaucer, but we can neglect it when we are reading St Bernard
or The Scale of Perfection or the Imitation. This is partly because the
spiritual books are entirely practical–like medical books. A man concerned
about the state of his soul will not usually be much helped by thinking
about the spheres or the structure of the atom.” Lewis, C.S. The Discarded
Image: An Introduction to Medieval and Renaissance Literature. 1964.
Cambridge University Press. P. 18.
“Nature may be the oldest of things, but Natura is the youngest of
deities. Really ancient mythology knows nothing of her. It seems to me
impossible that such a figure could ever arise in a genuinely mythopoeic
age; what we call ‘nature-worship’ has never heard of what we call
‘Nature.’ ‘Mother’ Nature is a conscious metaphor. ‘Mother’ Earth is
something quite different. All earth, contrasted with all the sky, can be,
indeed must be, intuited as a unity. The marriage relation between Father
Sky (or Dyaus) and Mother Earth forces itself on the imagination. He is on
top, she lies under him. He does things to her (shines and, more
important, rains upon her, into her): out of her, in response, come forth
the crops–just as calves come out of cows or babies out of wives. In a
word, he begets, she bears. You can see it happening. This is genuine
mythopoeia. But while the mind is working on that level, what, in heaven’s
name, is Nature? Where is she? Who has seen her? What does she do?
“The pre-Socratic philosophers of Greece invented Nature.” Lewis, C.S. The
Discarded Image: An Introduction to Medieval and Renaissance Literature.
1964. Cambridge University Press. P. 37.
“One is what I call the Principle of the Triad. The clearest statement of
it in Plato himself comes from the Timaeus: ‘it is impossible that two
things only should be joined together without a third. There must be some
bond in between both to bring them together’ (31b-c). The principle is not
stated but assumed in the assertion of the Symposium that god does not
meet man. They can encounter one another only indirectly; there must be
some wire, some medium, some introducer, some bridge–a third thing of some
sort–in between them. Daemons fill the gap. We shall find Plato himself,
and the medievals, endlessly acting on their principle; supplying bridges,
as it were, ‘third things’–between reason and appetite, soul and body,
king and commons.” Lewis, C.S. The Discarded Image: An Introduction to
Medieval and Renaissance Literature. 1964. Cambridge University Press. Pp.
43-4.
“The Medieval Model is, if we may use the word, anthropo-peripheral. We
are creatures of the Margin.” Lewis, C.S. The Discarded Image: An
Introduction to Medieval and Renaissance Literature. 1964. Cambridge
University Press. P. 58.
[To understand the Medieval Model, a reader must:] “He will find his whole
attitude to the universe inverted. In modern, that is, in evolutionary,
thought Man stands at the top of a stair whose foot is lost in obscurity;
in this, he stands at the bottom of a stair whose top is invisible with
light. He will also understand that something besides individual genius
(that, of course) helped to give Dante’s angels their unrivaled majesty.
Milton, aiming at that, missed the target. Classicism had come in between.
His angels have too much anatomy and too much armour, are too much like
the gods of Homer and Virgil, and (for that very reason) far less like the
gods of Paganism in its highest religious development. After Milton total
degradation sets in and we finally reach the purely consolatory, hence
waterishly feminine, angels of nineteenth-century art.” Lewis, C.S. The
Discarded Image: An Introduction to Medieval and Renaissance Literature.
1964. Cambridge University Press. Pp. 74-5.
“Whatever else a modern feels when he looks at the night sky, he certainly
feels that he is looking out–like one looking out from the saloon entrance
on to the dark Atlantic or from the lighted porch upon dark and lonely
moors. But if you accepted the Medieval Model you would feel like one
looking in. The Earth is ‘outside the city wall.’ When the sun is up he
dazzles us and we cannot see inside. Darkness, our own darkness, draws the
veil and we catch a glimpse of the high pomps within; the vast lighted
concavity filled with music and life.” Lewis, C.S. The Discarded Image: An
Introduction to Medieval and Renaissance Literature. 1964. Cambridge
University Press. Pp. 118-9.
“A glance at the Hereford mappemounde suggests that thirteenth-century
Englishmen were almost totally ignorant of geography. But they cannot have
been anything like so ignorant as the cartographer appears to be. For one
thing the British Isles themselves are one of the most ludicrously
erroneous parts of his map. Dozens, perhaps hundreds, of those who looked
at it when it was new, must at least have known that Scotland and England
were not separate islands; the blue bonnets had come over the border too
often to permit any such illusion. And secondly, medieval man was by no
means a static animal. Kings, armies, prelates, diplomats, merchants, and
wandering scholars were continually on the move. Thanks to the popularity
of pilgrimages even women, and women of the middle class, went far afield;
witness the Wife of Bath and Margery Kempe. A practical knowledge of
geography must have been pretty widely diffused. But it did not, I
suspect, exist in the form of maps or even of map-like visual images. It
would be an affair of winds to be waited for, landmarks to be picked up,
capes to be doubled, this or that road to be taken at a fork. I doubt
whether the maker of the mappemounde would have been at all disquieted to
learn that many an illiterate sea-captain knew enough to refute his map in
a dozen places. I doubt whether the sea-captain would have attempted to
use his superior knowledge for any such purpose. A map of the whole
hemisphere on so small a scale could never have been intended to have any
practical use. The cartographer wished to make a rich jewel embodying the
noble art of cosmography, with the Earthly Paradise marked as an island at
the extreme Easter edge (the East is at the top in this as in other
medieval maps) and Jerusalem appropriately in the center. Sailors
themselves may have looked at it with admiration and delight. They were
not going to steer by it.” Lewis, C.S. The Discarded Image: An
Introduction to Medieval and Renaissance Literature. 1964. Cambridge
University Press. Pp. 143-4.
“We have noticed that the term angels sometimes covers all the aetherial
beings and is sometimes resticted to the lowest of their nine species. In
the same way the word reason sometimes means Rational Soul, and sometimes
means the lower of the two faculties which Rational Sould exercises. These
are Intellectus and Ratio.
Intellectus is the higher, so that if we call it ‘understanding’, the
Coleridgean distinction which puts ‘reason’ above ‘understanding’ inverts
the traditional order. Boethius, it will be remembered, distinguishes
intelligentia from ratio; the former being enjoyed in its perfection by
angels. Intellectus is that in man which approximates most nearly to
angelic intelligentia; it is in fact obumbrata intelligentia, clouded
intelligence, or a shadow of intelligence. Its relation to reason is thus
described by Aquinas: ‘intellect (intelligere) is the simple (i.e.
indivisible, uncompounded) grasp of an intelligible truth, whereas
reasoning (ratiocinari) is the progression towards an intelligible truth
by going from one understood (intellecto) point to another. The difference
between them is thus like the difference between rest and motion or
between possession and acquisition’ (Ia, LXXIX, art. 8). We are enjoying
intellectus when we ‘just see’ a self-evident truth; we are exercising
ratio when we proceed step by step to prove a truth which is not
self-evident. A cognitive life in which all truth can be simply ‘seen’
would be the life in which all truth can be simply ‘seen’ would be the
life of an intelligentia, an angel. A life of unmitigated ratio where
nothing was simply ‘seen’ and all had to be proved, would presumably be
impossible; for nothing can be proved if nothing is self-evident. Man’s
mental life is spent in laboriously connecting those frequent, but
momentary, flashes of intelligentia which constitute intellectus.” Lewis,
C.S. The Discarded Image: An Introduction to Medieval and Renaissance
Literature. 1964. Cambridge University Press. Pp. 156-7.
"The Greek word theoria meant 'contemplation' and is the term used in
Aristotle's psychology to designate the moment of fully conscious
participation, in which the soul's potential knowledge (its ordinary
state) becomes actual, so that man can at last claim to be 'awake'. This
is no guide to its present, or even recent meaning, but it does emphasize
the difference between a proposition, the truth or untruth of which is
irrelevant. The geometrical paths and movements devised for the planets
were, in the minds of those who invented them, hypotheses in the latter
sense. They were arrangements--devices--for saving the appearances; and
the Greek and medieval astronomers were not at all disturbed by the fact
that the same appearances could be saved by two or more quite different
hypotheses, such as an eccentric or an epicycle or, particularly in the
case of Venus and Mercury, by supposed revolution round the earth or
supposed revolution round the sun. All that mattered was, which was the
simplest and the most convenient for practical purposes; for neither of
them had any essential part in truth or knowledge. Barfield, Owen. Saving
the Appearances: A Study of Idolatry, Harcourt Brace, p. 49.
"It is important to realize that in physics today, we have no knowledge of
what energy is. ...there can be any amount of energy, at least as
presently understood. So we do not understand this energy as counting
something at the moment, but just as a mathematical quantity, which is an
abstract and rather peculiar circumstance." Feynman, Richard. The Feynman
Lectures on Physics, Addison-Wesley Publishing Co., 1975, pp. 4-2 - 4-7.
"...one can respond to this human/nature dualism by attempting to draw the
human into the realm of nature, thus effectively eliminating subjectivity
altogether; or one can attempt to pull individual species of animals into
the realm of the human, and populate our landscape with the pets and
puppets that these pseudo-humans inevitably become. But to actually
encounter the other beings as other, as living subjects of significance,
requires some loosening of the conceptual bindings of nature so that
subjectivity can flow back in, like water to a scorched garden. This is
resisted in the everyday defense of dualism and by the strictures of
empirical investigation which dictate that we treat nature 'as an invading
army treats an occupied country, mixing as little as possible with the
inhabitants.'
"Yet here is the paradox: although we treat nature as the antithesis of
order, we also attribute to it a secret order. That is, by claiming
that there is a reasonable, regular structure behind all the appearances
of nature, an order discernible only by the human mind, we also claim it
for our own system; we have ordered it by claiming privileged
access to the 'system' within. By 'systemizing' nature, we make it ours, a
part of the ordered world, a part of culture. So, curiously, we both
accept it--the hidden part at least--as an ordered realm, while
simultaneously rejecting the 'dirty' manifestations of that hidden
order that are actually encountered in the chaotic domain that strives
against the backyard fence. Given this, perhaps the only action a
concerned person could take in support of the nonhuman world is to
demonstrate a tolerance of the 'divine chaos'--including weeds and dirt.
To do so would not only expand the habitat of innumerable creatures, but
would also confront the system that sustains this organic apartheid."
"Wildness, however, lies beyond the objects in question, a quality which
directly confronts and confounds our designs. At root, it is wildness
that is at issue: not wilderness, not polar bears, not whooping cranes or
Bengal tigers, but that which they as individuals exemplify. These
creatures are 'made of' wildness, one might say, before they are made of
tissue or protein. But perhaps even wildness is an inadequate term, for
that essential core of otherness is inevitably nameless, and as such
cannot be subsumed within our abstractions or made part of the domain of
human willing."
When Richard Jefferies concluded, at the end of a life of trying to
understand the creatures he so greatly admired, that he could not 'know'
nature, he liberated himself from a lifelong deceit. In doing so, he also
freed nature, as if he were releasing a songbird. He gave up the pretense
to knowledge that delimits what a creature may be, and which protects us
thereafter from the uncertainties of strangeness: we hide from wildness by
making it 'natural.' Inevitably, what we know is largely our own symbolic
representations, which will behave as they were designed to. But of that
which they purport to represent, they tell a partial story at best."
Evernden, Neil. The Social Creation of Nature. John Hopkins University
Press. 1992. pp. 108-9, 119, 121, 129.
"If the early modern natural philosopher or Renaissance physician
conducted an exegesis of the text of nature written in the language of
geometry or of cosmic correspondences, the postmodern scientist still
reads for a living, but has as a text the coded systems of recognition -
prone to the pathologies of mis-recognition - embodied in objects like
computer networks and immune systems. The extraordinary close tie of
language and technology could hardly be overstressed in postmodernism. The
'construct' is at the centre of attention; making, reading, writing, and
meaning seem to be very close to the same thing. This near-identity
between technology, body, and semiosis suggests a particular edge to the
mutually constitutive relations of political economy, symbol, and science
that 'inform' contemporary research trends in medical anthropology.
Bodies, then, are not born; they are made. Bodies have been as thoroughly
denaturalized as sign, context, and time. Late twentieth-century bodies do
not grow from internal harmonic principles theorized within Romanticism.
Neither are they discovered in the domains of realism and modernism. One
is not born a woman, Simone de Beauvoir correctly insisted. It took the
political-epistemological terrain of postmodernism to be able to insist on
a co-text to de Beauvoir's: one is not born an organism. Organisms are
made; they are constructs of a world-changing kind. The constructions of
an organisms's boundaries, the job of the discourses of immunology, are
particularly potent mediators of the experiences of sickness and death for
industrial and post-industrial people." Haraway, Donna J. Simians, Cyborgs,
and Women: The Reinvention of Nature. Routledge. 1991, Pp. 207-8.
"The movement toward a 'postmechanistic' paradigm, a paradigm suitable for
twenty-first-century science, is taking place across a broad front: in
cosmology, in the chemistry of self-organizing systems, in the new physics
of chaos, in quantum mechanics and particle physics, in the information
sciences and (more reluctantly) at the interface of biology with physics.
In all these areas scientists have found it fruitful, or even essential,
to regard the portion of the Universe they are studying in entirely new
terms, terms that bear little relation to the old ideas of materialism and
the cosmic machine. This monumental paradigm shift is bringing with it a
new perspective on human beings and their role in the great drama of
nature." Davies, Paul & J. Gribbin. The Matter Myth. Simon & Schuster,
1991, p. 8,
"Muslim fundamentalism is an enormously simple, powerful, earthy,
sometimes cruel, absorbing, socially fortifying movement, which gives a
sense of direction and orientation to millions of men and women, many of
whom live lives of bitter poverty and are subject to harsh oppression. It
enables them to adjust to a new anonymous mass society by identifying with
the old, long-established High Culture of their own faith, and explaining
their own deprivation and humiliation as a punishment for having strayed
from the true path, rather than a consequence of never having found it; a
disruption and disorientation is thus turned into a social and moral
ascension, an attainment of identity and dignity.
"Postmodernism, by contrast, is a tortuous, somewhat affected fad,
practiced by at most some academics living fairly sheltered lives; large
parts of it are intelligible only and at most (and often with difficulty)
to those who are fully masters of the nuances of three or four abstruse
academic disciplines, and much of it is not intelligible to anyone at all.
But it happens to be the currently fashionable form of relativism, and
relativism as such is an important intellectual option, and one which will
continue to haunt us, even if the form it assumes will vary - probably
with great speed - with the rapid turn-over of academic modes. Relativism
was approached through its current avatar in the interests of a certain
concreteness.
"And yet, though so very incomparable, the two specimens chosen do provide
a neat contrast in the logic of their ideas. First, a simple and
uncompromising monotheism, maintaining that God has made His Will easily
accessible and known to the world and that His Will is to be implemented,
and to constitute the only possible base of a uniquely just and legitimate
social order. An absolute Authority, severely external to this world and
its various cultures, dictates Its Will to Its Creation: and that
transcendent Will derives its legitimacy precisely from its unsullied,
extraneous and absolute origin. The firmness, simplicity and
intelligibility of the doctrine gives it dignity. Millions find it
satisfying to live under its rules: that must signify something.
"Next, there is a movement which denies the very possibility of extraneous
validity and authority. Admittedly, it is specially insistent in this
denial, when the contrary affirmation of such external validation comes
from fellow-members, non-relativists within their own society.
Relativist pudeur and ex-colonial guilt expiation on the other hand
inhibit stressing the point to members of other cultures. The
absolutism of others receives favoured treatment, and a warm
sympathy which is very close to endorsement.
"Knowledge or morality outside culture is, it claims, a chimera: each
culture must roll its own knowledge and morality. Meanings are
incommensurate, meanings are culturally constructed, and so all cultures
are equal. Cross-cultural or cross-semantic investigation is only possible
if the dignity and equality of the 'other' culture is respected. If it
were characterized and dissected with lucidity and confidence, this would
constitute at the very least an implied devaluation of it. So it must be
studied with tremulous obscurity, with confused and contradictory
approaches. So obscurity is turned into a sign, not merely of putative
depth, but of intercultural respect and abstention from domination....
"The relativists-hermeneutists are really very eager to display their
universal, ecumenical tolerance and comprehension of alien cultures. The
more alien, the more shocking and disturbing to the philistines, to those
whom they deem to be the provincialists of their own society, the better.
Very, very much the better, for the more shocking the other, the more does
this comprehension highlight the superiority of the enlightened
hermeneutist within his own society. The harder the comprehension, the
more repellent the object destined for hermeneutic blessing, the greater
the achievement, the illumination and the insight of the interpretive
postmodernist. However, our hermeneutist has to pussy-foot a bit around
the fact that those whom he would so eagerly tolerate and understand are
not always quite so tolerant themselves. The relativist endorses the
absolutism of others, and so his relativism entails an absolutism which
also contradicts it....
"The fundamentalists, on the other hand, are not very much concerned with
our relativists. I doubt whether they give them a great deal of thought.
What they have noticed is that the society which harbours hermeneutists,
as it harbours so much else (it can afford it), is pervaded by pluralism,
doubt, half-heartedness and an inability to take its own erstwhile faith
literally and practice it to the full. They are not quite clear whether
they despise it for its tolerance, or rebuke it for not being tolerant
enough, notably of their own intransigence:....
"There is a position which shares something with each of the two previous
protagonists, but it is also endowed with features profoundly
distinguishing it from them. What is it?
"It is a position which, like that of the religious fundamentalists, is
firmly committed to the denial of relativism. It is committed to the view
that there is external, objective, culture-transcending knowledge: there
is indeed 'knowledge beyond culture'. All knowledge must indeed be
articulated in some idiom, but there are idioms capable of formulating
questions in a way such that answers are no longer dictated by the
internal characteristics of the idiom or the culture carrying it but, on
the contrary, by an independent reality. The ability of cognition to reach
beyond the bounds of any one cultural cocoon, and attain forms of
knowledge valid for all - and, incidentally, an understanding of nature
leading to an exceedingly powerful technology - constitutes the central
fact about our shared social conditions.
"This position, on the other hand, also does have something in common with
our relativists: it does not believe in the availability of a substantive,
final, world-transcending Revelation. It does believe in the
existence of knowledge which transcends culture, and it is also
committed to the mundane origin of knowledge and its fallible status; but
it firmly repudiates the very possibility of Revelation. It does
not allow any cultures to validate a part of itself with final authority,
to decree some substantive affirmation to be privileged and exempt from
scrutiny....
"Enlightenment Rationalist Fundamentalism, of which I am a humble
adherent, repudiates any substantive revelations. It repudiates that
substantive absolutization so characteristic of some post-Axial world
religions which attribute an extra-mundane and trans-cultural standing and
authority to given substantive affirmations and values; and, to this
extent, at any rate, it resembles our relativists....
"The precise details of scientific method, of the cognitive procedure
discovered in the course of the Scientific Revolution and codified by the
Enlightenment, continue to be contentious. But in rough outline, it is
possible to specify them: there are no privileged or a priori
substantive truths. (This, at one fell swoop, eliminates the sacred
from the world.) All facts and all observers are equal. There are no
privileged Sources or Affirmations, and all of them can be queried. In
inquiry, all facts and all features are separable: it is always
proper to inquire whether combinations could not be other than what had
previously been supposed....
"The mild rationalist fundamentalism which is being commended does not
attempt, as the Enlightenment did, to offer a rival counter-model to its
religious predecessor. It is fundamentalist only in connection with the
form of knowledge, and perhaps in the form of morality, insisting on
symmetry of treatment for all. Otherwise, on all points of detail and
content, it compromises. This, if you like, is its concession to nihilism,
its similarity to relativism. Where no good reasons are available one can
go along with the contingencies of local development, the accidents of
local balance of power and taste. Serious knowledge is not subject to
relativism, but the trappings of our cultural life are." Gellner, Ernest.
Postmodernism, Reason and Religion. Routledge, 1992, pp. 72-95.
“The
notorious Liu Ling (ca. 221-300) used to go naked in his house. To a
shocked Confucian visitor he retorted, ‘The world is my house, and these
walls are my garments. What, then, are you doing standing in my pants?’”
Collins, Randall. The Sociology of Philosophies: A Global Theory of
Intellectual Change. 1998. Harvard University Press. P. 171.
“According to Leibniz, relation gave rise to substance, not, as Newton had
it, the other way around. Our universe had been selected from an infinity
of possible universes, explained Leibniz, so that a minimum of laws would
lead to a maximum diversity of results. God was the supreme intelligence
at both extremes of the scale. As Olaf Stapledon would later put it, ‘God,
who created all things in the beginning, is himself created by all things
in the end.’” Dyson, George. Darwin among the Machines: The Evolution of
Global Intelligence. 1997. Perseus Books. Pp. 35-6.
“The foundational quarrel of intellectual perspectives in Western culture
is the one between the rhetoricians and the philosophers.” Lanham,
Richard. The Economics of Attention: Style and Substance in the Age of
Information. 2006. University of Chicago Press. P. 27.
“In the hominization of the primates, there is a logarithmic progression
in the rates of evolutionary changes. Hominization, from primate to
hominin, takes place over millions of years – from Proconsul to Archaic
Homo sapiens. Symbolization takes place over hundreds of thousands of
years, from roughly 200,000 BCE to 20,000 BCE. Agriculturalization occurs
over thousands of years, from 10,000 BCE to 3500 BCE. Civilization takes
place also over thousands of years from 3500 BCE to the fifteenth century
CE. Industrialization takes place over centuries from the fifteenth to the
late nineteenth and twentieth centuries, but Planetization takes place
over decades, sped up by electronics and genetic engineering – or from
natural selection to cultural intrusion.” Thompson, William I. “Natural
Drift and the Evolution of Culture.” Journal of Consciousness Studies. 14,
No. 11, 2007. Pp. 96-116. P. 100.
“Only one real difference distinguishes a scientific theory from a
religious doctrine, but it is an important one. In science, we are
supposed to search deliberately for data that undermines our theories. In
this way we test our theories and eliminate those that do not fit the
facts. In religion, we attempt, almost as deliberately, to ignore or
reject any data that contradicts the doctrine.” Burling, Robbins. The
Talking Ape: How Language Evolved. 2005. Oxford University Press. P. 229.
“... at its core, to think of oneself as modern is to define one’s being
in terms of time. This is remarkable. In previous ages and other places,
people have defined themselves in terms of their land or place, their race
or ethnic group, their traditions or their gods, but not explicitly in
terms of time. Of course, any self-understanding assumes some notion of
time, but in all other cases the temporal moment has remained implicit.
Ancient peoples located themselves in terms of a seminal event, the
creation of the world, an exodus from bondage, a memorable victory, or the
first Olympiad, to take only a few examples, but locating oneself
temporally in any of these ways is different than defining oneself in
terms of time. To be modern means to be ‘new,’ to be an unprecedented
event in the flow of time, a first beginning, something different than
anything that has come before, a novel way of being in the world,
ultimately not even a form of being but a form of becoming. To understand
oneself as new is also to understand onself as self-originating, as free
and creative in a radical sense, not merely as determined by a tradition
or governed by fate or providence. To be modern is to be self-liberating
and self-making, and thus not merely to be in a history or tradition but
to make history. To be modern consequently means not merely to define
one’s being in terms of time but also to define time in terms of one’s
being, to understand time as the product of human freedom in interaction
with the natural world. Being modern at its core is thus something
titanic, something Promethean.” Gillespie, Michael Allen. The Theological
Origins of Modernity. 2008. University of Chicago Press. P. 2.
“Petrarch’s thought is a response to the crisis of late medieval
civilization. He finds an answer to this crisis in a vision of man as a
finite individual capable of self-mastery and self-perfection. However,
for Petrarch such self-mastery is only possible outside of political life.
At its foundations, the modern notion of the individual and thus the
modern age is intensely private and apolitical.” Gillespie, Michael Allen.
The Theological Origins of Modernity. 2008. University of Chicago Press.
Pp. 46-7.
“According to Petrarch, only virtue can make us victorious in our
never-ending war with fortune. Fortune batters us continually with its two
weapons, prosperity and adversity, and the wounds these weapons inflict
are the passions or affects. Struck by the passions, we cease to be
masters of ourselves and are pulled this way and that.” Gillespie, Michael
Allen. The Theological Origins of Modernity. 2008. University of Chicago
Press. P. 51.
“Petrarch was convinced by his encounter with scholasticism that morality
could not rest merely on true knowledge. Human beings had to will moral
action. Humans thus had to have a moral purpose and want to attain it.
Thinking in this sense is the pursuit of the good. The moral problem that
thought confronts in a world that is characterized by strife rather than
order, however, is that there are no natural ends for humans to pursue.”
Gillespie, Michael Allen. The Theological Origins of Modernity. 2008.
University of Chicago Press. P. 52.
“As a result of his quarrel with Luther, Erasmus fell into a pessimism
from which he never entirely recovered. His pessimism was justified.
Humanism would continue to exercise an important influence on
intellectuals and on some members of the upper classes, but as an agent of
social change it had been surpassed by the religious passions unleashed
first by the Reformation and then a few years later by the
Counter-reformation. These passions reached a much broader population than
humanism and moved them in more immediate and more violent ways. The
humanist project in which Erasmus had placed such great hopes would be
revived, but only in a world that had been radically transformed by the
Wars of Religion, the exploration and colonization of the New World, the
Copernican Revolution, and the development of a new mathematical natural
science. The intervening period was a time of unparallel violence and
religious fanaticism. Humanism would survive in a variety of forms and
places, but it was generally driven from the public square into private
towers and Epicurean gardens, out of ducal courts into secret societies
and the privacy of individual households.” Gillespie, Michael Allen. The
Theological Origins of Modernity. 2008. University of Chicago Press. Pp.
167-8.
“Descartes saw man as res extensa but also as res cogitans. He did not
thereby mean to suggest that human bodies were not subject to natural
causes but only that they were also moved by a free human will. Hobbes, by
contrast, argues that humans are governed by the same mechanical causality
that governs all beings. He rejects the idea that humans have a
supernatural component as a ploy of priests to gain power over others.”
Gillespie, Michael Allen. The Theological Origins of Modernity. 2008.
University of Chicago Press. P. 234.
“As we discussed above, Hobbes denies that we have a free will. However,
he does not therefore subscribe to the Lutheran doctrine that man is
nothing other than an ass ridden by God or the devil. There is no freedom
God bestows on us with an infusion of his will. Hobbes believes such pious
hopes merely subordinate us to the passions of priests and religious
fanatics. Humans are bodies driven by passions, and to be free for Hobbes
is to pursue the objects of our passions without external constraints.
This is practical but not metaphysical freedom. Human beings are the
motions that are imparted to them. Like all other beings they are
manifestations of divine will that foreknows and forewills every event.
While we are thus predestined to be the kinds of beings we are and to have
the passions that we have, this does not affect our freedom because it is
precisely these passions that define our identity.” Gillespie, Michael
Allen. The Theological Origins of Modernity. 2008. University of Chicago
Press. P. 236.
“For Hobbes reason means something different than what it did for his
predecessors. It is not a separate power that can discern the appropriate
ends of life and guide us in the proper direction. It is thus not
teleological but instrumental, the spy and scout of the passions. It thus
helps us to maximize the satisfaction of our desires but not to train,
direct, or control them. To live by right reason, for Hobbes, is thus not
an end but a means.” Gillespie, Michael Allen. The Theological Origins of
Modernity. 2008. University of Chicago Press. P. 236.
“Kant first considered the problem of the antinomies in his dissertation,
[but] he did not appreciate their full significance until after reading
Hume. In the period before he began writing the Critique of Pure Reason
(1781), he came to understand their deeper significance. He explained this
in a letter to Garve on September 26, 1798, asserting that it was ‘not the
investigation of the existence of God, of immortality, etc. but the
antinomy of pure reason ... from which I began.” ‘The world has a
beginning –: it has no beginning, etc., to the fourth[?] There is freedom
in human being,–against there is no freedom and everything is natural
necessity’; it was this that first woke me from my dogmatic slumber and
drove me to the critique of reason itself to dissolve the scandal of the
contradiction of reason with itself.’ The central reference here is to the
Third Antinomy (the seventy-four year old Kant misspeaks himself in his
reference to the Fourth Antinomy). This antinomy purports to show that it
is impossible to give a meaningful causal explanation of the whole without
the assumption of a first cause through freedom, and yet that the very
possibility of such freedom undermines the necessity of any causal
explanation. In other words, modern natural science, which analyzes all
motion in terms of efficient causes, is unintelligible without a freely
acting first cause such as God or man, but such causality through freedom,
which is essential to morality, is incompatible with natural necessity.
Freedom is thus both necessary to causality and incompatible with it. Kant
recognized that if this conclusion were correct, the modern project was
self-contradictory and that modern reason could give man neither the
mastery of nature nor the freedom that he so desired.” Gillespie, Michael
Allen. The Theological Origins of Modernity. 2008. University of Chicago
Press. P. 259.
“As we have seen, modernity in the broadest sense was a series of attempts
to answer the fundamental questions that arose out of the nominalist
revolution. These questions were both profound and comprehensive, putting
into doubt not merely the knowledge of God, man, and nature, but reason
and being as well. The humanist movement and the Reformation were
comprehensive attempts to answer these questions. They both accepted the
nominalist ontology of radical individualism, but they disagreed ontically
about which of the traditional realms of being was foundational. The
humanists began their account with man and interpreted the other realms of
being anthropomorphically. The Reformers, by contrast, believed that God
was primary and interpreted man and nature theologically. As we have seen,
however, neither the humanists nor the Reformers were willing to eliminate
either God or man. The humanists did not suggest that God did not exist,
and the Reformers did not deny the independence of human beings. However,
such qualifications, especially in times of persecution, are often merely
camouflage for deeper claims. To the extent that their differences were
foundational, each position denied the ground of the other, as we saw in
our examination of the debate between Erasmus and Luther. If one begins as
Erasmus does with man and asserts even a minimal efficacy for human
freedom, divine omnipotence is compromised and the reality of the
Christian God is called in question. Morality in this way renders piety
superfluous. If one begins with a doctrine of divine freedom and
omnipotence manifested as divine grace, no human freedom is possible.
Religion crushes morality and transforms human beings into mere
marionettes, The Luther/Erasmus debate thus actually ends in the same
unsatisfying juxtaposition of arguments as the later Kantian antinomy. If
we were to schematize that debate in a logical form corresponding to the
antinomy, the thesis position (represented by Erasmus) would be that there
is causality through human freedom in addition to the causality through
divine will, and the antithesis position (represented by Luther) that
there is no causality through human freedom but only through divine will.
There is no solution to this problem on either a humanistic or a
theological basis that can sustain both human freedom and divine
sovereignty. As we saw above, the gulf that is opened up by this
contradiction was unbridgeable. It was also unavoidable since each claim
is parasitic on the other. This antinomy, which played an important role
in propelling Europe into the Wars of Religion, was thus in a certain
sense inevitable.” Gillespie, Michael Allen. The Theological Origins of
Modernity. 2008. University of Chicago Press. Pp. 261-2.
“As prototypical modern thinkers, both Descartes and Hobbes agree that in
our analysis of the world we must grant ontic priority to nature. Insofar
as they represent opposing poles within modernity, they disagree about the
way in which we should interpret the human and the divine within this
naturalistic horizon. As we have seen, Descartes sees human beings as
corporeal (res extensa) and thus as comparable to all other natural
beings, but he also sees humans as incorporeal (res cogitans) and thus as
comparable to God. Hobbes, by contrast, argues that human beings are no
different than the rest of nature, mere bodies in motion that can no more
act like God than create something out of nothing. Descartes is thus able
to retain a space for human freedom, while Hobbes concludes that
everything happens as the result of necessity.” Gillespie, Michael Allen.
The Theological Origins of Modernity. 2008. University of Chicago Press.
Pp. 262-3.
“For Descartes, the human body is a mechanical thing, but the human self
or soul is independent of this realm and its laws, a res cogitans, a
thinking thing. For Hobbes, man like all other created beings is matter in
motion and nothing besides.” Gillespie, Michael Allen. The Theological
Origins of Modernity. 2008. University of Chicago Press. P. 266.
“If we are essentially incorporeal, then true knowing cannot be derived
from the images formed as a result of our interactions with bodies. For
Descartes, the realm of pure thought is thus independent of body and of
the corporeal imagination. In the fourth objection, Hobbes denies the
possibility of such non-imagistic thinking. Reasoning, he argues, is a
connecting of names, and names are merely the signs of images. We have no
immediate or even mediate knowledge of what is. Words are merely tools
that we use to obtain power over and manipulate things. Therefore, as
Hobbes tells us elsewhere, all thinking is hypothetical and is measured
not by its truth or correspondence to what ultimately is, but by its
effectiveness. For Descartes by contrast, we reason not about words but
about the objects that they signify, and mathesis universalis aims not
merely at probably knowledge that gives us an effective mastery of nature
at this time and place but at apodictic knowledge that can guarantee our
mastery everywhere and always.
“If Hobbes is correct about the nature of reasoning, then as Descartes
well knows, we can never be certain that our ideas correspond to the
things themselves. For Descartes, the guarantee of such a correspondence
is provided by God, but only if God is not a deceiver. Mathesis
universalis thus depends on the demonstration of this fact, but such a
demonstration itself depends on our being able to know God, on having an
idea of God in us. Hobbes considers this impossible because God is
infinite, and all of our ideas are drawn from the imagination of finite
bodies.” Gillespie, Michael Allen. The Theological Origins of Modernity.
2008. University of Chicago Press. Pp. 266-7.
“Viewed from this perspective, the process of secularization or
disenchantment that has come to be seen as identical with modernity was in
fact something different than it seemed, not the crushing victory of
reason over infamy, to use Voltaire’s famous term, not the long drawn out
death of God that Nietzsche proclaimed, and not the evermore distant
withdrawal of the deus absconditus Heidegger points to, but the gradual
transference of divine attributes to human beings (an infinite human
will), the natural world (universal mechanical causality), social forces
(the general will, the hidden hand), and history (the idea of progress,
dialectical development, the cunning of reason).” Gillespie, Michael
Allen. The Theological Origins of Modernity. 2008. University of Chicago
Press. Pp. 272-3.
“The German Romantics, early German idealists, and their
nineteenth-century followers were convinced that the Enlightenment had
misconstrued nature as a mechanical rather than as an organic or spiritual
process. They believed that if nature were grasped in a pantheistic
fashion as the product of a world-spirit (Goethe), a world-soul (Emerson),
and absolute I (Fichte), or a primordial will (Schelling, Schopenhauer),
it would be compatible with human freedom, since both natural motion and
human action would spring from a common source. The real barrier to human
freedom in their view lay not in nature but in the institutions and
practices that had been created and propagated by the Enlightenment with
its dedication to a mechanistic understanding of nature, universal rights,
bureaucratic politics, the development of commerce, and bourgeois
morality. True human freedom for these thinkers thus could only be
attained by expressing one’s will (including one’s natural passions and
desires) regardless of the consequences for social, political, or moral
order. The truly free ‘natural’ man thus asserts his will against all
bounds and consequently appears to enlightened society to be a moral
monster (Tieck’s William Lovell, Byron’s Manfred, Goethe’s Faust) or a
criminal (Stendhal’s Julian Sorel, Balzac’s Vautrin, Shelley’s
Prometheus). A life led in harmony with nature is a life in contradiction
to convention. To live in this way it is thus necessary to liberate
oneself from Enlightenment rationalism and reconceptualize nature as the
motion of spirit rather than the motion of matter. Hence in place of
reason these thinkers put passion or will; in place of mathematics, art;
in place of universal rights, national mores; and in place of the
bureaucratic state, the charismatic leader. Romantic nationalism and later
Fascism and Nazism were among the consequences of this development.
“In contrast to these thinkers, natural scientists such as Michael Faraday
and James Clerk Maxwell sought to give a comprehensive account that saw
the motion of matter as the result of the interplay of natural forces.
This led to the development of the chemical and physical sciences, but
also, and more importantly, to a new biological science that tied the
development of man to the chemical and physical development of the
universe as a whole. In the first instance this took the form of an
evolutionary theory that saw man as a moment in the development of life as
such, but this was followed in the twentieth century by a molecular
biology that saw life itself as merely a subset of material motion. In
this way the distinctiveness of humans and of life itself was effaced, as
the difference between the animate and inanimate was eliminated.”
Gillespie, Michael Allen. The Theological Origins of Modernity. 2008.
University of Chicago Press. Pp. 278-9.
“Thus we cannot characterize political ecology by way of a crisis of
nature, but by way of a crisis of objectivity. The risk-free objects, the
smooth objects to which we had been accustomed up to now, are giving way
to risky attachments, tangled objects.” Latour, Bruno. Politics of Nature:
How to Bring the Sciences into Democracy. 2004. Harvard University Press.
Translated by Catherine Porter. P. 22.
“Far from globalizing all that is at stake under the auspices of nature,
the practice of political ecology can be recognized precisely by the
ignorance it turns out to manifest about the respective importance of the
actors. Political ecology does not shift attention from the human pole to
the pole of nature; it shifts from certainty about the production of
risk-free objects to uncertainty about the relations whose unintended
consequences threaten to disrupt all orderings, all plans, all impacts.
What it calls back into question with such remarkable effectiveness is
precisely the possibility of collecting the hierarchy of actors and
values, according to an order fixed once and for all. An infinitesimal
cause can have vast effects; an insignificant actor becomes central; an
immense cataclysm disappears as if by magic; a miracle product turns out
to have nefarious consequences; a monstrous being is tamed without
difficulty. With political ecology, one is always caught off-guard, struck
sometimes by the robustness of systems, sometimes by their fragility.”
Latour, Bruno. Politics of Nature: How to Bring the Sciences into
Democracy. 2004. Harvard University Press. Translated by Catherine Porter.
P. 25.
“Now, it is precisely in its failures, when it deploys matters of concern
with unanticipated forms that make the use of any notion of nature
radically impossible, that political ecology is finally doing its own job,
finally innovating politically, finally bringing us out of modernism,
finally preventing the proliferation of smooth, risk-free matters of fact,
with their improbable cortege of incontestable knowledge, invisible
scientists, predictable impacts, calculated risks, and unanticipated
consequences.” Latour, Bruno. Politics of Nature: How to Bring the
Sciences into Democracy. 2004. Harvard University Press. Translated by
Catherine Porter. P. 27.
“As soon as we add to dinosaurs their paleontologists, to particles their
accelerators, to ecosystems their monitoring instruments, to energy
systems their standards and the hypothesis on the basis of which
calculations are made, to the ozone holes their meteorologists and their
chemists, we have already ceased entirely to speak of nature; instead, we
are speaking of what is produced, constructed, decided, defined, in a
learned City whose ecology is almost as complex as that of the world it is
coming to know. By proceeding in this way, we add the history of the
sciences, shorter but even more eventful, to the infinitely long history
of the planet, the solar system, and the evolution of life. The billions
of years since the Big Bang date from the 1950s; the pre-Cambrian era
dates from the mid-nineteenth century; as for the particles that make up
the universe, they were all born in the twentieth century. Instead of
finding ourselves facing a nature without history and society with a
history, we find ourselves thus already facing a joint history of the
sciences and nature. Each time one risks falling into fascination with
nature, one has only, in order to sober up, to add the network of the
scientific discipline that allows us to know nature.” Latour, Bruno.
Politics of Nature: How to Bring the Sciences into Democracy. 2004.
Harvard University Press. Translated by Catherine Porter. P. 35.
“This paradox has been noted often: the concern for the environment begins
at the moment when there is no more environment, no zone of reality in
which we could casually rid ourselves of the consequences of human
political, industrial, and economic life. This historical importance of
ecological crises stems not from a new concern with nature but, on the
contrary, from the impossibility of continuing to imagine politics on one
side and, on the other, a nature that would serve politics simultaneously
as a standard, a foil, a reserve, a resource, and public dumping ground.”
Latour, Bruno. Politics of Nature: How to Bring the Sciences into
Democracy. 2004. Harvard University Press. Translated by Catherine Porter.
P. 58.
“Let us remember that non-humans are not in themselves objects, and still
less are they matters of fact. They first appear as matters of concern, as
new entities that provoke perplexity and thus speech in those who gather
around them, discuss them, and argue over them.” Latour, Bruno. Politics
of Nature: How to Bring the Sciences into Democracy. 2004. Harvard
University Press. Translated by Catherine Porter. P. 66.
“We are thus going to associate the notion of external reality with
surprises and events, rather than with the simple ‘being-there’ of the
warrior tradition, the stubborn presence of matters of fact.” Latour,
Bruno. Politics of Nature: How to Bring the Sciences into Democracy. 2004.
Harvard University Press. Translated by Catherine Porter. P. 79.
“How should we designate the associations of humans and non-humans of this
collective in the process of coming together? The term I have been using
up to now is very awkward, for no one imagines addressing a black hole, an
elephant, an equation, or a jet engine, with the resounding label
‘citizen’! We need a new term that has no whiff of the Old Regime about
it, one that allows us to recapitulate in a single expression the speech
impedimenta, the uncertainty about actions, and also the variable degrees
of reality that define civil life from now on. I am offering the term
propositions: I am going to say that a river, a troop of elephants, a
climate, El Niño, a mayor, a town, a park, have to be taken as
propositions to the collective. The word has the advantage of being able
to pull together the meanings of the four preceding sections. ‘I have a
proposition for you’ indicates uncertainty and not arrogance; it is the
peace offering that puts an end to war; it belongs to the realm of
language now shared by humans and nonhumans alike; it indicates
wonderfully that what is in question is a new and unforeseen association,
one that is going to become more complicated and more extended;” Latour,
Bruno. Politics of Nature: How to Bring the Sciences into Democracy. 2004.
Harvard University Press. Translated by Catherine Porter. P. 83.
“It is not because they know what must be done and not done that the
moralists can contribute to the civic virtues, then, but only because they
know that everything that will be done well will necessarily be done
badly, and as a result will have to be done over again right away. ‘No one
knows what an environment can do,’ ‘no one knows what associations define
humanity,’ ‘no one can assume the right to classify ends and means once
and for all, the right to lay down the boundary between necessity and
freedom without discussion’–such are the concerns that the moralists are
going to introduce into all the procedures of the collective.” Latour,
Bruno. Politics of Nature: How to Bring the Sciences into Democracy. 2004.
Harvard University Press. Translated by Catherine Porter. P. 156.
“Let us not forget the fairy Carabosse! On the pile of gifts offered by
her sisters, she put down a little casket marked Calculemus! But she did
not specify who was supposed to calculate. It was thought that the best of
all possible worlds was calculable, provided that the labor of politics
could be short-circuited. This was enough to spoil all the other virtues,
given how much heroism would have been needed to resist the attractions of
that facile approach. Now, neither God nor men nor nature forms at the
outset the sovereign capable of carrying out this calculation. The
requisite ‘we’ has to be produced out of whole cloth. No fairy has told us
how. It is up to us to find out.” Latour, Bruno. Politics of Nature: How
to Bring the Sciences into Democracy. 2004. Harvard University Press.
Translated by Catherine Porter. P. 164.
“Modernism thought itself highly virtuous because it thought it did not
have to eliminate excluded parties from the collective through violence.
It was content to note, sanctimoniously, their radical nonexistence in the
form of fictions, beliefs, irrationalities, nonsense, lies, ideologies, or
myths. In this we can clearly see the extent of its perversion: it thought
itself more moral because it did not believe it had any enemies, while it
was so thoroughly scornful of those it excluded that it considered them
lacking in any real existence at all! The accusation of irrationality made
it possible to reject beings, to consign them to limbo, without due
process, and to believe this arbitrariness more just than the meticulous
procedure of the State of law ... A hefty dose of audacity is required to
prefer this exclusion based on the nature of things–on the things of
nature–over an explicit, progressive, deliberative process of excluding
certain entities for the time being as incompatible with the common world.
“The second manner, that of the lower house, has the immense advantage of
being civil: if it creates enemies for itself, it does not claim to
humiliate them by withdrawing existence, in addition to their presence in
the collective, from them. It simply tells them this: ‘In the scenarios
attempted up to now, there is no room for you in the common world. Go
away: you have become our enemies.’ But it does not say to them, draped in
its cloak of high morality: ‘You do not exist; you have lost forever any
right to ontology; you will never again be counted in the construction of
a cosmos’–which modernism, imbued to the core with virtue, repeated to
them over and over without the slightest scruple. By excluding, the lower
house trembles at the possibility of committing an injustice, for it knows
that the enemies that threaten to put it in danger one day can become its
allies the next.” Latour, Bruno. Politics of Nature: How to Bring the
Sciences into Democracy. 2004. Harvard University Press. Translated by
Catherine Porter. Pp. 178-9.
“I have sought to explore a different solution. Instead of eliminating the
requirements that bear on the constitution of the facts by sending them
back to the private sphere, why not, on the contrary, lengthen the list of
these requirements? The seventeenth-century solution, the simultaneous
invention of indisputable matters of fact and of endless discussion,
ultimately did not offer sufficient guarantees for the construction of the
public order, the cosmos. The two most important functions were lost: the
capacity to debate the common world, and the capacity to reach agreement
by closing the discussion–the power to take into account along with the
power to put in order....
“If we need less Science, we need to count much more on the sciences; if
we need fewer indisputable facts, we need much more collective
experimentation on what is essential and what is accessory. Here, too, I
am asking for just a tiny concession: that the question of democracy be
extended to nonhumans. But is this not at bottom what the scientists have
always most passionately wanted to defend: to have absolute assurance that
facts are not constructed by mere human passions? They believed too
quickly that they had reached this goal by the short-cut of matters of
fact kept from the outset apart from all public discussion.” Latour,
Bruno. Politics of Nature: How to Bring the Sciences into Democracy. 2004.
Harvard University Press. Translated by Catherine Porter. P. 223.
“Emergentism is a form of nonreductionism that accepts the ontological
position of materialism. With regard to the complex natural phenomena
under study, emergentism accepts that nothing exists except the component
parts and their interactions, and thus it avoids the ontological problems
of holism. However, the emergentist also rejects atomism and argues that
reductionism, physicalism, mechanism, and epiphenomenalism are not
necessary consequences of materialism. Some complex natural phenomena
cannot be studied with reductionist methods; these phenomena are complex
systems in which more complex and differentiated ‘higher-level’ structures
emerge from the organization and interaction of simpler, ‘lower-level’
component parts.” Sawyer, R. Keith. Social Emergence: Societies as Complex
Systems. 2005. Cambridge University Press. P. 29.
“Bergson referred to the human tendency to fixate on stable forms as the
‘cinematographical illusion,’ a metaphor for the false belief that reality
is a succession of fixed structures.” Sawyer, R. Keith. Social Emergence:
Societies as Complex Systems. 2005. Cambridge University Press. P. 33.
“How can a theory represent reality objectively if fundamental features of
its representation, such as the number of objects it postulates, can vary
from one interpretation to another? Model-theoretic considerations thus
played a significant role in the transition to internal realism. Putnam
now maintains that for the metaphysical realist who believes there must be
an objective criterion singling out a uniquely correct reference relation
from a range of possibilities, the model-theoretic problem, the problem of
the availability of multiple interpretations, is insurmountable. From the
perspective of internal realism, however, reference, being an essential
component of our conceptual apparatus, is unproblematic; it cannot and
need not be anchored in ‘objective’ reality by yet another layer of
theory.” Ben-Menahem, Yemima. Hilary Putnam. 2005. Cambridge University
Press. P. 7.
“Taken together, these mind-boggling concepts comprise the participatory
anthropic principle. The principle offers an explanation for the
life-friendly qualities of our cosmos that is, at least superficially,
diametrically opposed to the notion encapsulated in the strong anthropic
principle (i.e., that the laws of nature were somehow fine-tuned from the
outset to eventually yield life and intelligence). In Wheeler’s remarkable
vision, the device that fine-tunes the universe consists not of a precise
initial blueprint, but of a vast assembly of billions upon billions of
living observer-participants, the overwhelming majority of whom inhabit
the distant future. It is the collective and retroactive effect of their
countless acts of observation that reaches backward in time and creates
our world, along with all of its physical laws and constants.” Gardner,
James. Biocosm: The New Scientific Theory of Evolution: Intelligent Life
is the Architect of the Universe. 2003. Inner Ocean Publishing. P. 45.
“It is no exaggeration to say that the Newtonian worldview is in tatters.
Unfortunately, surprisingly few of us seem willing to admit this
condition. It is poignant to ask, therefore, what has arisen that can take
the place of the Newtonian framework. As we shall see, there have been a
number of thinkers who have suggested fertile new directions, but none has
been accorded widespread attention. Rather, what one encounters among the
scientific community is that most of us by and large cling to some
dangling threads of the Newtonian worldview. It’s just that there remains
no widespread consensus about how much weight, if any, should be given to
each assumption.” Ulanowicz, Robert. A Third Window: Natural Life beyond
Newton and Darwin. 2009. Templeton Foundation Press. P. 25.
“The limits on Darwinian theory are related to the antagonism between
change and the goals of science. Whereas science aims to codify, simplify,
and predict, the interjection of chance into the narrative results in
conspicuous exceptions to regularity, complications in specifying the
system, and degradation of the ability to predict. In the last chapter, we
discussed two instances (statistical mechanics and the grand synthesis) of
how science has attempted to mitigate the challenges posed by stochastic
interference. Both reconciliations rested upon the same mathematical
tool–probability theory–to retrieve some degree of regularity and
predictability over the long run....”
“Because probability theory works only on simple, generic, and repeatable
chance, most tacitly assume that all instances of chance share these
characteristics. But, if the burgeoning field of ‘complexity theory’ has
taught us anything, it is that matters cannot always be considered simple.
Complex systems exist, so why shouldn’t complex chance? In fact, as
regards living systems, it seems fair to assert that complexity is more
the rule than the exception. Are complex chance events to be precluded
from the discourse on nature, as if they don’t exist, just because they
don’t conform to known methods for measuring and regularizing?” Ulanowicz,
Robert. A Third Window: Natural Life beyond Newton and Darwin. 2009.
Templeton Foundation Press. Pp. 42-3.
“Most recent estimates agree that there are about 1081 simple
particles throughout all of known space. Now the simplest physical events
we can observe would happen to the simplest of particles over an interval
that is characteristic of subatomic events (about a nanosecond or a
billionth of a second). Because the universe has been around for some
13-15 billion years, or about 1023 nanoseconds, Elsasser,
therefore, concluded that at the very most 1081 X 1023,
or 10106 simple events could have transpired. One can safely
conclude that anything with less than one in 10106 chances of
reoccurring simply is never going to do so, even over many repetitions of
the lifetime of our universe. The take-home lesson is that one should be
very wary whenever one encounters any number greater than 10106
or smaller than 10-106 because such frequencies simply cannot
apply to any known physical reality. Elsasser calls any number exceeding
10106 an enormous number....”
“... one asks how many different types or characteristics are required
before a random combination can indisputably be considered unique....”
“Reliable uniqueness happens to require only about seventy-five distinct
tokens because the combinations of types scale roughly as the factorial of
their number. Because 75! = 10106, whenever more than
seventy-five distinguishable events co-occur by chance, one can be certain
that they will never randomly do so again.” Ulanowicz, Robert. A Third
Window: Natural Life beyond Newton and Darwin. 2009. Templeton Foundation
Press. Pp. 44-5.
“Elsasser’s result is important to ecologists because it is almost
impossible for anyone dealing with real ecosystems to consider one that is
composed of fewer than seventy-five distinguishable individuals.”
Ulanowicz, Robert. A Third Window: Natural Life beyond Newton and Darwin.
2009. Templeton Foundation Press. P. 45.
“As mentioned, in order to estimate a legitimate probability of an event,
that event must reoccur at least several times. If an event is unique for
all time, it evades treatment by probability theory. Now if the density of
unique events overwhelms that of simple ones, as it does in complex
systems, then most of reality lies beyond the ken of probability theory.”
Ulanowicz, Robert. A Third Window: Natural Life beyond Newton and Darwin.
2009. Templeton Foundation Press. Pp. 46-7.
“To delve deeper into the insufficiency of physical laws, we turn to
Elsasser’s second argument as to why they cannot apply to biology.
Elsasser stresses the heterogeneity inherent in biological systems. He
notes that, in physics, one always deals with a continuum, whereas, in
biology, the dominant concept is that of a class (such as a taxonomic
species or an ontogenetic stage)....”
“More specifically, Whitehead and Russell proved that lawful behavior
within the continuum can correspond only to operations between perfectly
homogeneous sets.” Ulanowicz, Robert. A Third Window: Natural Life beyond
Newton and Darwin. 2009. Templeton Foundation Press. Pp. 48-9.
“Although the metaphysic [exaggerated materialism] arose out of the
palpable need to put as much distance as possible between the activities
of the scientist and anything transcendental, it is legitimate to ask
whether far more distance was placed between the two than was necessary.
The separation became a veritable chasm–an abyss that far exceeded the
requirements of methodological naturalism. It could be said of the ensuing
gulf that it was so wide that it swallowed any number of perfectly natural
phenomena, most notably, life.” Ulanowicz, Robert. A Third Window: Natural
Life beyond Newton and Darwin. 2009. Templeton Foundation Press. P. 137.
“... there also exist gaps that are part of the formal structure of
science, which reflect the ontic openness of nature. Examples include
Goedel’s incompleteness theorem, Heisenberg’s uncertainty principle, the
Pauli exclusion principle, and Elsasser’s unique events.” Ulanowicz,
Robert. A Third Window: Natural Life beyond Newton and Darwin. 2009.
Templeton Foundation Press. P. 159.
“Causes act primarily bottom-up at microscales, whereas top-down influence
provides more relevant explanation at higher levels.” Ulanowicz, Robert. A
Third Window: Natural Life beyond Newton and Darwin. 2009. Templeton
Foundation Press. P. 165.
“What
nature uses is not a Law of Pattern but a palette of principles. And
there is, I submit, much more wonder in a world that weaves its own
tapestry using countless elegant and subtle variations, combinations and
modifications of a handful of common processes, than one in which the
details become irrelevant and in which a few recondite equations are
supposed to explain everything.” Ball, Philip. Nature’s Patterns: A
Tapestry in Three Parts - Branches. 2009. Oxford University Press.
P. 180.
“Spontaneous patterns typically represent a
compromise between forces that impose conflicting demands.” Ball,
Philip. Nature’s Patterns: A Tapestry in Three Parts - Branches.
2009. Oxford University Press. P. 182.
“Competition lies at the heart of the
beauty and complexity of natural pattern formation. If the competition is
too one-sided, all form disappears, and one gets either unstructured,
shifting randomness, or featureless homogeneity–bland in either event.
Patterns live on the edge, in a fertile borderland between these extremes
where small changes can have large effects.” Ball, Philip. Nature’s
Patterns: A Tapestry in Three Parts - Branches. 2009. Oxford
University Press. P. 183.
“Thus, stripe-like patterns are often the
first to appear from a uniform, flat system. That is what we see for sand
ripples and in the appearance of convection and Taylor-Couette roll cells.
“After breaking symmetry periodically in
one dimension, the next ‘minimal’ pattern in a two-dimensional system
involves breaking it in the other, dividing up the system into
compartments or grids. If the state is to remain ordered and as symmetric
as possible, there are only two options: to impose the periodic variation
perpendicular to the rolls, creating square cells, or to impose two such
variations at 60o angles, creating triangles or hexagons. So
the square, triangular and hexagonal patterns that we have seen in Turing
patterns, in convection and in shaken sand are no mystery. They arise
simply because the geometric properties of space constrain the ways
in which symmetry can be broken.” Ball, Philip. Nature’s Patterns: A
Tapestry in Three Parts - Branches. 2009. Oxford University Press.
P. 198.
“Ten years ago, when I began writing
Probabilistic Reasoning in Intelligent Systems (1988), I was working
within the empiricist tradition. In this tradition, probabilistic
relationships, constitute the foundations of human knowledge, whereas
causality simply provides useful ways of abbreviating and organizing
intricate patterns of probabilistic relationships. Today, my view is
quite different. I now take causal relationships to be the fundamental
building blocks both of physical reality and of human understanding of
that reality, and I regard probabilistic relationships as but the surface
phenomena of the causal machinery that underlies and propels our
understanding of the world.
“Accordingly, I see no greater impediment
to scientific progress than the prevailing practice of focusing all of our
mathematical resources on probabilistic and statistical inferences while
leaving causal considerations to the mercy of intuition and good
judgment.” Pearl, Judea. Causality: Models, Reasoning, and Inference.
2000. Cambridge University Press. Pp. xiii-xiv.
“The philosopher Bertrand Russell made this
argument in 1913:
“‘All philosophers,’ says Russell,
‘imagine that causation is one of the fundamental axioms of science, yet
oddly enough, in advanced sciences, the word ‘cause’ never occurs.... The
law of causality, I believe, is a relic of bygone age, surviving, like the
monarchy, only because it is erroneously supposed to do no harm.’
“Another philosopher, Patrick Suppes, who
argued for the importance of causality, noted that:
“‘There is scarcely an issue of ‘Physical
Review’ that does not contain at least one article using either ‘cause’ or
‘causality’ in its title.’
“What we conclude from this exchange is
that physicists talk, write, and think one way and formulate physics in
another.” Pearl, Judea. Causality: Models, Reasoning, and Inference.
2000. Cambridge University Press. P. 337.
“Take, for instance, Newton’s law:
“F = ma.
“The rules of algebra permit us to write
this law in a wild variety of syntactic forms, all meaning the same thing
– that if we know any two of the three quantities, the third is
determined.
“Yet, in ordinary discourse we say that
force causes acceleration – not that acceleration causes force, and we
feel very strongly about this distinction.” Pearl, Judea. Causality:
Models, Reasoning, and Inference. 2000. Cambridge University Press.
P. 338.
“Deep understanding means knowing
not merely how things behaved yesterday but also how things will behave
under new hypothetical circumstances, control being one such
circumstance. Interestingly, when we have such understanding we feel ‘in
control’ even if we have no practical way of controlling things. For
example, we have no practical way to control celestial motion, and still
the theory of gravitation gives us a feeling of understanding and control,
because it provides a blueprint for hypothetical control. We can predict
the effect on tidal waves of unexpected new events – say, the moon being
hit by a meteor or the gravitational constant suddenly diminishing by a
factor of 2 – and, just as important, the gravitational theory gives us
the assurance that ordinary manipulation of earthly things will not
control tidal waves. It is not surprising that causal models are viewed
as the litmus test for distinguishing deliberate reasoning from reactive
or instinctive response. Birds and monkeys may possibly be trained to
perform complex tasks such as fixing a broken wire, but that requires
trial-and-error training. Deliberate reasoners, on the other hand, can
anticipate the consequences of new manipulations without ever trying
those manipulations.” Pearl, Judea. Causality: Models, Reasoning, and
Inference. 2000. Cambridge University Press. Pp. 345-6.
“If you wish to include the entire universe
in the model, causality disappears because interventions disappear – the
manipulator and the manipulated loose their distinction. However,
scientists rarely consider the entirety of the universe as an object of
investigation. In most cases the scientist carves a piece from the
universe and proclaims that piece in – namely, the focus of
investigation. The rest of the universe is then considered out or
background and is summarized by what we call boundary conditions.
This choice of ins and outs creates asymmetry in the way we
look at things, and it is this asymmetry that permits us to talk about
‘outside intervention’ and hence about causality and cause-effect
directionality.
“This can be illustrated quite nicely using
Descartes’ classical drawing [human pointing at an object and perceiving
it through eyeballs connected through nerves to hand which is overlaid by
two boxes one of which captures hand and object and the other of which
captures the eyeballs and nerves]. As a whole, this hand-eye system knows
nothing about causation. It is merely a messy plasma of particles and
photons trying their very best to obey Schroedinger’s equation, which is
symmetric.
“However, carve a chunk from it – say, the
object part – and we can talk about the motion of the hand causing
this light ray to change angle.
“Carve it another way, focusing on the
brain part, and lo and behold it is now the light ray that causes the hand
to move – precisely the opposite direction. The lesson is that it is the
way we carve up the universe that determines the directionality we
associate with cause and effect. Such carving is tacitly assumed in every
scientific investigation. In artificial intelligence it was called
‘circumscription’ by J. McCarthy. In economics, circumscription amounts
to deciding which variables are deemed endogenous and which exogenous,
in the model or external to the model.
“Let us summarize the essential differences
between equational and causal models. Both use a set of symmetric
equations to describe normal conditions. The causal model, however,
contains three additional ingredients: (i) a distinction between the in
and the out; (ii) an assumption that each equation corresponds to
an independent mechanism and hence must be preserved as a separate
mathematical sentence; and (iii) interventions that are interpreted as
surgeries over those mechanism[s]. This brings us closer to realizing the
dream of making causality a friendly part of physics. But one ingredient
is missing: the algebra. We discussed earlier how important the
computational facility of algebra was to scientists and engineers in the
Galilean era. Can we expect such algebraic facility to serve causality as
well? Let me rephrase it differently: Scientific activity, as we know it,
consists of two basic components:
“Observations and interventions.”
“The combination of the two is what we call
a laboratory, a place where we control some of the conditions and
observe others.” Pearl, Judea. Causality: Models, Reasoning, and
Inference. 2000. Cambridge University Press. Pp. 349-351.
“Geometrically, a causal network can be
represented by a directed graph with nodes for variables, e.g. X and Y of
data and directed edges X -> Y as causal relations. If no common causes
are omitted from a set of variables, the set is causally sufficient. A
network is acyclic if there are no connected sequences of arrows in the
same direction that enters and exits the same node. A node with no edge
directed into it is called exogenous or an independent variable.” Mainzer,
Klaus. “Causality in Natural, Technical, and Social Systems.” 2010.
European Review. Vol. 18, No. 4, 433-454. P. 436.
“For each pair of variables X and Y, there
are four possible kinds of causal networks:
1. X -> Y, non X <- Y
2. Y
-> X, non X-> Y
3. X
-> Y, Y -> X
4.
non X -> Y, non Y -> X
“In general, the number of possible causal
models of n variables is 4 raised to the power of the number of
pairs [of] variables (e.g., for three variables, 43; for four
variables, 46; for five, 410;...” Mainzer, Klaus.
“Causality in Natural, Technical, and Social Systems.” 2010. European
Review. Vol. 18, No. 4, 433-454. Pp. 437-8.
“Control is the inverse problem of
causality for engineers.” Mainzer, Klaus. “Causality in Natural,
Technical, and Social Systems.” 2010. European Review. Vol. 18,
No. 4, 433-454. P. 445.
“Neural nets can represent causal
behavioral patterns as probability relations corresponding to cognitive
stimuli or responses.” Mainzer, Klaus. “Causality in Natural, Technical,
and Social Systems.” 2010. European Review. Vol. 18, No. 4,
433-454. P. 446.
“In computer technology, it is a challenge
to guarantee the causality between input and output of data streams and to
avoid causal loops with endless repetitions. Data streams of input and
output channels I and O describe the I/O-behavior
F of information systems. The I/O-behavior F is
deterministic if for each input x there is exactly one output
F(x). The timing of inputs and outputs depends on the chosen scaling
of time intervals. F is called weakly causal if the output in the
tth time interval does not depend on input that is received after
time t. F is called strongly causal if the output in the
tth time interval does not depend on input that is received after the
(t-1)th interval. In this case, F reacts to input received
in the (t-1)th interval. Thus, causality between input and output
is guaranteed.” Mainzer, Klaus. “Causality in Natural, Technical, and
Social Systems.” 2010. European Review. Vol. 18, No. 4,
433-454. P. 448.
“Descartes and
his contemporaries were living in a culture saturated by Aristotelianism,
where, if one was not a total sceptic, one was likely to believe that the
external world actually possessed the properties ascribed to it by an
observer, so that anything which, for example, looked red was really red,
in the same sense that it might be said to be really a certain size or
shape.
“Descartes, however, denied this, without becoming a complete sceptic.
Instead, he insisted that there need be no resemblance between what we
experience and the external world: the sequence of images that constitutes
our continuous life of perception does not necessarily represent in a
picture-like way the world outside us. In The World he used the analogy of
language: words refer to objects, but they do not resemble them; in the
same way, he argued, visual images or other sensory inputs relate to
objects without depicting them. The external world is in fact incapable of
being experienced in its true character. By contrast, we can have an
absolutely compelling knowledge of our own internal life, and of the
images which flicker in front of us.
“The difference between Descartes and a sceptic arose from this last
point, and it is a subtle but nevertheless crucial divergence. For the
sceptics, the fact that one person thought an apple was green and another
thought it was brown illustrated our incapacity to know the truth: the
apple, they believed, must be a determinate colour, but human perception
could not decide what it was. To that extent, the sceptic was still a kind
of Aristotelian, who simply insisted on the irremediable character of
human fallibility: an ideal, non-human observer might see the world as it
really was, and it would still be a world of colours, smells, tastes, and
so on. Descartes, on the other hand, argued that we have no reason to
suppose that there are colours, etc., in the real, external world at all,
and therefore no reason to conclude that colour-blindness (for example)
means that we cannot know the truth about that world. Colour is solely an
internal phenomenon, caused no doubt by something external, but neither
fallibly nor infallibly representing it.” Tuck, Richard. Hobbes: A Very
Short Introduction. 1989. Oxford University Press. Pp. 20-1.
“For Bacon, but not for Aristotle, the causes of material processes are
themselves material – they are no different in kind from their effects –
and one thing a method should provide is a means of working back from
manifest physical effects to their underlying physical causes.” Gaukroger,
Stephen. Francis Bacon and the Transformation of Early-Modern Philosophy.
2001. Cambridge University Press. P. 135.
“Natural philosophy, for Aristotle, was concerned to explain the
properties of things in terms of their essences. What lies at the basis of
his schema is the distinction between those things that have an intrinsic
principle of change, and those things that have an extrinsic principle of
change. Acorns, and stones raised above the ground, both come in the first
category; the former has within itself the power to change its state, into
an oak tree, the latter has the power to change its position, to fall to
the ground. In neither case is anything external required for the
change/motion to occur. Aristotle thought that we explain and understand
things by understanding their natures, where to give the nature of
something is to give the ultimate characterisation of it. If we ask why a
stone falls, the answer is that stones are heavy and heavy things fall:
That is all there is to it. If we are asked why this tree puts out broad
flat leaves in spring and keeps them through the summer, we may reply that
it does this because it is a beech. In other words, we do not feel it is
necessary to look outside the thing to account for its behaviour. And
wherever we feel that we can explain a thing’s behaviour, partly at least,
without looking outside the thing, we think that its behaviour, and the
feature that it acquires or retains, is natural. It is natural for stones
to fall, it is the nature of beeches to have broad flat leaves. Such
explanations are explanations of unconstrained, internally generated
natural processes, and explanations of this kind lie at the core of
Aristotle’s natural philosophy. Unnatural or constrained or ‘violent’
states and processes might be caused by any number of extrinsic processes,
and natural philosophy cannot be expected to account for these: A stone
falling to the ground when released from constraints has a single
explanation which refers us to an intrinsic cause, whereas a stone rising
from the ground can have any number of causes, and natural philosophy
cannot be expected to enumerate or account for these. This does not mean
that Aristotle does not deal with violent motions at all, but they are not
the central cases for his analysis and they cannot be dealt with in a
systematic way.” Gaukroger, Stephen. Francis Bacon and the Transformation
of Early-Modern Philosophy. 2001. Cambridge University Press. Pp. 136-7
(Note).
“In natural philosophy, Aristotle makes explanations prior to causes. His
famous ‘four causes’ are in fact four kinds of explanation, the
combination of which is designed to yield a complete understanding of the
phenomenon. If we know what something is, what it is made from, how it was
made, and for what end it was made, we have a complete understanding of
the phenomenon.” Gaukroger, Stephen. Francis Bacon and the Transformation
of Early-Modern Philosophy. 2001. Cambridge University Press. P. 149.
“I have further argued that Descartes separated metaphysics from natural
theology by making the eternal truths more radically dependent on God than
had others before him. In a deft bit of metaphysics, he explained how we
can have knowledge of the essences of natural things without insight into
the divine mind. Metaphysics and physics were to proceed without claiming
any special knowledge of God’s purposes and without presupposing
comprehension of God’s creative power. Descartes effectively widened the
range of the natural light with respect to the world but narrowed it with
respect to God.” Hatfield, Gary. “Reason, Nature, and God in Descartes.”
Pp. 259-287. From Voss, Stephen. Essays on the Philosophy and Science of
Rene Descartes. 1993. Oxford University Press. Pp. 277-8.
“Unlike a substance, an actant is not distinct from its qualities, since
for Latour this would imply an indefensible featureless lump lying beneath
its tangible properties.” Harman, Graham. Prince of Networks: Bruno Latour
and Metaphysics. 2009. Re.press. P. 17.
“If the most obscure Popperian zealot talks of ‘falsification’, people are
ready to see a profound mystery. But if a window cleaner moves his head to
see whether the smear he wants to clean is on the inside or the outside,
no one marvels.” Latour, Bruno. The Pasteurization of France. 1988.
Harvard University Press. P. 217. Quoted in: Harman, Graham. Prince of
Networks: Bruno Latour and Metaphysics. 2009. Re.press. P. 31.
“For Latour, modernity is the impossible attempt to create a radical split
between objective natural fact and arbitrary human perspective.” Harman,
Graham. Prince of Networks: Bruno Latour and Metaphysics. 2009. Re.press.
P. 31.
“Fact construction is so much a collective process that an isolated person
builds only dreams, claims and feelings, not facts.” Latour, Bruno.
Science in Action: How to Follow Scientists and Engineers Through Society.
1987. Harvard University Press. P. 41. Quoted in: Harman, Graham. Prince
of Networks: Bruno Latour and Metaphysics. 2009. Re.press. P. 50.
“Here we find a tension between events and trajectories that Latour’s
metaphysics never fully resolves. An event happens in a single time and
place and is fully concrete, since it cannot be analyzed into essential
and inessential elements. This entails that even the tiniest shift in a
thing’s interactions, as always occurs in every moment, suffices to
transform an event into something altogether new. Whether I jump, unbutton
my shirt, or lose the least hair from my head, my existence in each case
will become an entirely different event, since Latour leaves no room to
speak of ‘accidental’ variation in the same enduring thing. For this
reason, events are effectively frozen into their own absolutely specific
location and set of relationships, and cannot possibly endure outside
them. By contrast, the notion of trajectories teaches the opposite lesson.
When considering a trajectory, we never find a thing in a single time and
place, but get to know it only by following its becomings, watching the
details of its curriculum vita. We learn of the successive trials from
which it emerges either victorious or stalemated. And here is the paradox:
in one sense, Latour’s objects are utterly imprisoned in a single instant;
in another sense, they burst all boundaries of space and time and take off
on lines of flight toward ever new adventures.” Harman, Graham. Prince of
Networks: Bruno Latour and Metaphysics. 2009. Re.press. P. 65.
“Relationism, the view that a thing is defined solely by its effects and
alliances rather than by a lonely inner kernel of essence, is the
paradoxical heart of Latour’s position, responsible for all his
breakthroughs and possible excesses....”
“... Let those who attack Latour attack him for relationsism, and not on
false charges of antirealism and social constructionism.” Harman, Graham.
Prince of Networks: Bruno Latour and Metaphysics. 2009. Re.press. P. 75.
“Why is it that academics who claim to seek the truth want to pretend that
they have always had it? What are they paid for, anyway?” Wimsatt,
William. Re-Engineering Philosophy for Limited Beings: Piecewise
Approximations to Reality. 2007. Harvard University Press. P. 3.
“Any adequate account of reason must see it as the adaptation that it is:
fallible, but self-correcting. And self-correcting not just through reason
alone, but in the way that DNA is self-replicating–when embedded in a
larger supporting complex that is both of the world and self-continuing in
the world.” Wimsatt, William. Re-Engineering Philosophy for Limited
Beings: Piecewise Approximations to Reality. 2007. Harvard University
Press. P. 7.
“Generative entrenchment (GE) is a third deep principle of adaptive
design. A deeply generatively entrenched feature of a structure is one
that has many other things depending on it because it has played a role in
generating them. It is an inevitable characteristic of evolved systems of
all kinds–biological, cognitive, or cultural–that different elements of
the system show differential entrenchment.” Wimsatt, William.
Re-Engineering Philosophy for Limited Beings: Piecewise Approximations to
Reality. 2007. Harvard University Press. Pp. 133-4.
“New systems that facilitate mechanisms by which some elements can come to
play a generative or foundational role relative to others are always
pivotal innovations in the history of evolution, as well as–much more
recently–in the history of ideas. Mathematics, foundational theories,
generative grammars, and computer programs attract attention as
particularly powerful ways of organizing and producing complex knowledge
structures and systems of behavior. They not only produce or accumulate
downstream products, but they do so systematically and relatively easily.
Once they appear, generative systems become pivotal in any world where
evolution is possible: biological, psychological, scientific,
technological, or cultural. Generative systems come to dominate in
evolution, and are rapidly retuned and refined for increasing efficiency,
replication rate, and fidelity, as soon as they are invented.” Wimsatt,
William. Re-Engineering Philosophy for Limited Beings: Piecewise
Approximations to Reality. 2007. Harvard University Press. P. 135.
“Mathematical biologist Jack Cowan loves to describe the difference
between biophysicists and theoretical biologists. A university president
once said to him: ‘You both use a lot of math and physics to do
biology–you must be doing the same thing. Why shouldn’t I merge your
departments?’
“‘I’ll tell you the difference,’ Cowan said, ‘take an organism and
homogenize it in a Waring blender. The biophysicist is interested in those
properties that are invariant under that transformation.’” Wimsatt,
William. Re-Engineering Philosophy for Limited Beings: Piecewise
Approximations to Reality. 2007. Harvard University Press. Pp. 174-5.
“What if some properties of the parts and system were invariant no matter
how you cut it up, aggregated, or rearranged its parts? For such
properties, organization wouldn’t matter. There are such properties–those
picked out by the great conservation laws of physics: mass, energy,
charge, and so forth. As far as we know, that’s all. These meet very
restrictive conditions: for any decompositions of the system into parts,
these properties are invariant over appropriate rearrangements,
substitutions, and re-aggregations, and their values scale appropriately
under additions or subtractions to the system. Meeting these conditions
makes them very important properties–properties that became the source of
the great unifications of nineteenth-century physics. For these
aggregative properties, we are willing to say: ‘The mass of that steer I
gave you was nothing more than the mass of its parts.’ And we blame the
butcher–not vanished emergent interactions–for any shortfalls. If these
four conditions (informally stated above) are met for all possible
decompositions of the system into parts, aggregativity must be an
extremely demanding relationship, one seldom found in nature.” Wimsatt,
William. Re-Engineering Philosophy for Limited Beings: Piecewise
Approximations to Reality. 2007. Harvard University Press. P. 175.
“Descriptive complexity has a point, largely because of what I call
interactional complexity. This is a measure of the complexity of the
causal interactions of a system, with special attention paid to those
interactions that cross boundaries between one theoretical perspective and
another.
“Many systems can be decomposed into subsystems for which the
intra-systemic causal interactions are all much stronger than the
extra-system ones. This is the concept of ‘near-complete decomposability’
described by Simon and others.” Wimsatt, William. Re-Engineering
Philosophy for Limited Beings: Piecewise Approximations to Reality. 2007.
Harvard University Press. P. 184. Reference is to Simon, Herbert. “The
Architecture of Complexity.” Proceedings of the American Philosophical
Society. 106(6): 467-482.
“Naive design procedures in engineering, in which the organization of the
designed system was made to correspond to the conceptual breakdown of the
design problem into different functional requirements, with a 1-1
correspondence between physical parts and functions, have given way to
more sophisticated circuit minimization and optimal design techniques.
These methods have led to increases in efficiency and reliability by
letting several less complicated parts jointly perform a function that had
required a single more complicated part, and, where possible,
simultaneously letting these simpler parts perform more than one function
(in what might before have been distinct functional subsystems). This has
the effect of making different functional subsystems more interdependent
than they had been before, and of encouraging still further specialization
of function, and interdependence of parts. It is reasonable to believe
that the optimizing effects of selection do just this for evolving
systems, and if so, that hierarchically aggregating systems will tend to
lose their neat S-decomposability by levels and become interactionally
complex.
“This argument is buttressed empirically by considering what happens when
natural organized systems are artificially decomposed into subassemblies
that are the closest modern equivalents of the subassemblies from which
the systems presumably came. Few modern men could survive for long outside
of our specialized society. The same goes for mammalian cells–at least
under naturally occurring conditions, even though multi-cellular organisms
are presumably descended from unicellular types. Even many bacteria cannot
survive and reproduce outside of a reasonably sized culture of similar
bacteria. The current belief of some biologists is that mitochondria and
chloroplasts originated as separate organisms, and acquired their present
role in animal and plant cells via parasitic or symbiotic association.
According to this view these once independent organisms (or subassemblies)
are now so totally integrated with their host that only their independent
genetic systems are a clue to their origin.” Wimsatt, William.
Re-Engineering Philosophy for Limited Beings: Piecewise Approximations to
Reality. 2007. Harvard University Press. Pp. 188-9.
“But what holds true of an organism (that many boundaries coincide at its
skin) need not hold true of its parts. Inside the complex system there is
a hegemony of different constraints and perspectives and boundaries. If
what Campbell says is correct, this hegemony leads us to be slow or
dubious about objectifying the parts of such a system. What is
unobjectifiable is to that extent unphysical, and so functional
organization becomes a thicket for vital forces and mental entities. It is
no accident that those systems for which vitalisms and mentalisms have
received spirited defenses are those systems that are also
paradigmatically complex.”
“The difficulties with the spatial localization of function in complexly
organized systems suggest a more positive approach to at least one aspect
of the psychophysical identity thesis. In 1961, Jerome Shaffer took
account of the frequently discussed non-spatiality of mental events and
proposed that the spatial location of corresponding brain events could, as
a convention, be taken as the location of the corresponding mental
events.” Wimsatt, William. Re-Engineering Philosophy for Limited Beings:
Piecewise Approximations to Reality. 2007. Harvard University Press. P.
191. References: Campbell, Donald. “Common Fate, Similarity, and Other
Indices of the Status of Aggregates of Pesona s Social Entities.” 1958.
Behavioral Sciences. 3: 14-25. Shaffer, Jerome. “Could Mental States Be
Brain Processes?” Journal of Philosophy. 1961. 58: 813-822.
“Things are robust if they are accessible (detectable, measurable,
derivable, definable, producible, or the like) in a variety of independent
ways.” Wimsatt, William. Re-Engineering Philosophy for Limited Beings:
Piecewise Approximations to Reality. 2007. Harvard University Press. P.
196.
“Indeed, if the checks or means of detection are probabilistically
independent, the probability that they could all be wrong is the product
of their individual probabilities of failure, and this probability
declines very rapidly (i.e., the reliability of correct detection
increases rapidly) as the number of means of access increases, even if the
means are individually not very reliable.” Wimsatt, William.
Re-Engineering Philosophy for Limited Beings: Piecewise Approximations to
Reality. 2007. Harvard University Press. Pp. 196-7.
“It follows that our concept of an object is a concept of something that
is knowable robustly.” Wimsatt, William. Re-Engineering Philosophy for
Limited Beings: Piecewise Approximations to Reality. 2007. Harvard
University Press. P. 197.
“These networks [causal networks making up the world] should be viewed as
a sort of bulk causal matter–an undifferentiated tissue of causal
structures–in effect the biochemical pathways of the world, whose
topology, under some global constraints, yields interesting forms. Under
some conditions, these networks are organized into larger patterns that
comprise levels of organization, and under somewhat different conditions
they yield the kinds of systematic slices across which I have called
perspectives. Under some conditions, they are so richly connected that
neither perspectives nor levels seem to capture their organization, and
for this condition, I have coined the term causal thickets.” Wimsatt,
William. Re-Engineering Philosophy for Limited Beings: Piecewise
Approximations to Reality. 2007. Harvard University Press. P. 200.
“Diamond attempts global and integrated explanations of the rise and
character of civilizations essentially from this perspective, providing a
mix of contingencies and autocatalytic and hierarchically dependent
processes showing rich signs of generative entrenchment. Adaptations
(beginning with agriculture) causing and supporting increasing population
densities, cities, role differentiation and interdependencies, and
governments make generative entrenchment inevitable.” Wimsatt, William.
Re-Engineering Philosophy for Limited Beings: Piecewise Approximations to
Reality. 2007. Harvard University Press. P. 136. Reference is to Diamond,
Jared. Guns, Germs and Steel. 1997. W. W. Norton.
“The medieval university had had four faculties: theology, medicine, law,
and philosophy. What happened in the nineteenth century was that almost
everywhere, the faculty of philosophy was divided into at least two
separate faculties: one covering the ‘sciences’; and one covering other
subjects, sometimes called the ‘humanities,’ sometimes the ‘arts’ or
‘letters’ (or both), and sometimes retaining the old name of
‘philosophy.’” Wallerstein, Immanuel. World-Systems Analysis: An
Introduction. 2004. Duke University Press. P. 3.
“The sciences denied the humanities the ability to discern truth. In the
earlier period of unified knowledge, the search for the true, the good,
and the beautiful had been closely intertwined, if not identical. But now
the scientists insisted that their work had nothing to do with a search
for the good or the beautiful, merely the true.” Wallerstein, Immanuel.
World-Systems Analysis: An Introduction. 2004. Duke University Press. P.
3.
“Take ‘exploitation.’ In a recent book about it, Alan Wertheimer does a
splendid job of seeking out necessary and sufficient conditions for the
truth of statements of the form ‘A exploits B.’ He does not quite succeed,
because the point of saying that middle-class couples exploit surrogate
mothers, or that colleges exploit their basketball stars on scholarships–Wertheimer’s
prized examples–is to raise consciousness. The point is less to describe
the relation between colleges and stars than to change how we see those
relations. This relies not on necessary and sufficient conditions for
claims about exploitation, but on fruitful analogies and new perspectives.
“In the same way, a primary use of ‘social construction’ has been for
raising consciousness.” Hacking, Ian. The Social Construction of What?
1999. Harvard University Press. Pp. 5-6. Reference is to Wertheimer, Alan.
Exploitation. 1996. Princeton University Press.
“Social construction work is critical of the status quo. Social
constructionists about X tend to hold that:
“(1) X need not have existed, or need not be at all as it is. X, or X as
it is at present, is not determined by the nature of things; it is not
inevitable.
“Very often they go further, and urge that:
“(2) X is quite bad as it is.
“(3) We would be much better off if X were done away with, or at least
radically transformed.”
Hacking, Ian. The Social Construction of What? 1999. Harvard University
Press. P. 6.
“Ideas do not exist in a vacuum. They inhabit a social setting. Let us
call that the matrix within which an idea, a concept or kind, is formed.
‘Matrix’ is no more perfect for my purpose than the word ‘idea.’ It
derives from the word for ‘womb,’ but it has acquired a lot of other
senses–in advanced algebra, for example. The matrix in which the idea of
the woman refugee is formed is a complex of institutions, advocates,
newspaper articles, lawyers, court decisions, immigration proceedings. Not
to mention the material infrastructure, barriers, passports, uniforms,
counters at airports, detention centers, courthouses, holiday camps for
refugee children.” Hacking, Ian. The Social Construction of What? 1999.
Harvard University Press. P. 10.
“Here are names for six grades of constructionism.
“Historical
“Ironic
“Reformist Unmasking
“Rebellious
“Revolutionary
“The least demanding grade of constructionism about X is historical.”
Hacking, Ian. The Social Construction of What? 1999. Harvard University
Press. P. 19.
“If contingency is the first sticking point, the second one is more
metaphysical....”
“It is countered by a strong sense that the world has an inherent
structure that we discover....”
“Constructionists think that stability results from factors external to
the overt content of the science. This makes for the third sticking point,
internal versus external explanations of stability.”
“Each of these three sticking points is the basis of genuine and
fundamental disagreement. Each is logically independent of the others.
Moreover, each can be stated without using elevator words like ‘fact,’
‘truth,’ or ‘reality,’ and without closely connected notions such as
‘objectivity’ or ‘relativism.’ Let us try to stay as far as we can from
those blunted lances with which philosophical mobs charge each other in
the eternal jousting of ideas.” Hacking, Ian. The Social Construction of
What? 1999. Harvard University Press. P. 33.
“Looping effects are everywhere. Think what the category of genius did to
those Romantics who saw themselves as geniuses, and what their behavior
did in turn to the category of genius itself. Think about the
transformations effected by the notions of fat, overweight, anorexic. If
someone talks about the social construction of genius or anorexia, they
are likely talking about the idea, the individuals falling under the idea,
the interaction between the idea and the people, and the manifold of
social practices and institutions that these interactions involve: the
matrix, in short.” Hacking, Ian. The Social Construction of What? 1999.
Harvard University Press. P. 34.
“The constructionist argues that the product is not inevitable by showing
how it came into being (historical process), and noting the purely
contingent historical determinants of that process.” Hacking, Ian. The
Social Construction of What? 1999. Harvard University Press. P. 38.
“Kant was the great pioneer of construction.... Kant was truly radical in
his day, but he still worked within the realm of reason, even if his very
own work signaled the end of the Enlightenment. After his time, the
metaphor of construction has served to express many different kinds of
radical philosophical theory, not all of them dedicated to reason. But all
agree with Kant in one respect. Construction brings with it one or another
critical idea, be it the criticism of the Critique of Pure Reason or the
cultural criticisms advanced by constructionists of various stripes.”
Hacking, Ian. The Social Construction of What? 1999. Harvard University
Press. P. 41.
“Russell wanted to be able to state what we do know, without assuming the
existence of such things. That is where the notion of a logical
construction comes in....”
“What is the point? When an inferred entity X is replaced by a logical
construction, statements about X may be asserted without implying the
existence of X’s, since the logical form or deep structure of those
sentences makes no reference to X. We are allowed to talk about X’s while
being agnostic about the existence of X’s.” Hacking, Ian. The Social
Construction of What? 1999. Harvard University Press. Pp. 41-2.
“Let us record, however, that it has been a constant thrust in moral
theory, from Immanuel Kant’s categorical imperative to John Rawls’s theory
of justice and Michel Foucault’s self-improvement, to insist that the
demands of morality are constructed by ourselves, as moral agents, and
that only those we construct are consistent with the freedom that we
require as moral agents.” Hacking, Ian. The Social Construction of What?
1999. Harvard University Press. Pp. 46-7.
“Refuting a thesis works at the level of the thesis itself by showing it
to be false. Unmasking undermines a thesis, by displaying its
extra-theoretical function.” Hacking, Ian. The Social Construction of
What? 1999. Harvard University Press. P. 56.
“For sociologists the processes of science, the scientific activity,
should be the main object of study. But for scientists the most
controversial philosophical issues are about science, the product, the
assemblage of truths.” Hacking, Ian. The Social Construction of What?
1999. Harvard University Press. P. 67.
“Research scientists have theoretical models, speculative conjectures
couched in terms of those models; they also have views of a much more
down-to-earth sort, about how apparatus works and what you can do with it;
how it can be designed, modified, adapted. Finally, there is that
apparatus itself, equipment and instrumentation, some bought off the
shelf, some carefully crafted and some jerry-built as inquiry demands it.
Typically, the apparatus does not behave as expected. The world resists.
Scientists who do not simply quit have to accommodate themselves to that
resistance. They can do it in numerous ways. Correct the major theory
under investigation. Revise beliefs about how the apparatus works. Modify
the apparatus itself. The end product is a robust fit between all these
elements.” Hacking, Ian. The Social Construction of What? 1999. Harvard
University Press. P. 71.
“Formally speaking, the contingency thesis is entirely consistent with the
ultimate one-and-only picture upon which inquiry in the physical sciences
will converge. For there could be many roads to the one true ultimate
theory, or none at all. If there were many roads, then the physics at each
way station on each road would be different from the physics at way
stations on every other road.” Hacking, Ian. The Social Construction of
What? 1999. Harvard University Press. P. 78.
“Anyone antagonistic to both the letter and spirit of constructionism
could still agree that the truth of a scientific proposition in no way
explains why people maintain, hold, believe, or assent to that
proposition.” Hacking, Ian. The Social Construction of What? 1999. Harvard
University Press. P. 82.
“One party hopes that the world may, of its own nature, be structured in
the ways in which we describe it. Even if we have not got things right, it
is at least possible that the world is so structured. The whole point of
inquiry is to find out about the world. The facts are there, arranged as
they are, no matter how we describe them. To think otherwise is not to
respect the universe but to suffer from hubris, to exalt that pip-squeak,
the human mind.
“The other party says it has an even deeper respect for the world. The
world is so autonomous, so much to itself, that it does not even have what
we call structure in itself. We make our puny representations of this
world, but all the structure of which we can conceive lies within our
representations. They are subject to severe constraints, of course. We
have expectations of our interactions with the material world, and when
they are not fulfilled, we do not lie about it, to ourselves or anyone
else. In the fairly public domain of science, the cunning of apparatus and
the genius of theory serve to keep us fairly honest.” Hacking, Ian. The
Social Construction of What? 1999. Harvard University Press. P. 83.
“If we took the metaphor of ‘construction’ literally, we could hardly call
the Edinburgh school constructionist, but they certainly emphasize the
social. Latour, while saying more about how construction is done,
de-emphasizes the word ‘social,’ saying we have never been modern, never
in fact separated ths social from the natural. To the uncommitted, all
such writers emphasize factors in science which strike one as external to
the content of the sciences they describe....”
“All such protests are in vain at the tribunal of the physicist, because
Latour thinks that external factors are relevant to the stability of laws
of nature, while Weinberg thinks they are irrelevant.” Hacking, Ian. The
Social Construction of What? 1999. Harvard University Press. Pp. 90-1.
“Constructionists believe that there is an extra-theoretical function for
inevitablism, inherent-structurism, and the rejection of external
explanations of the stability of the sciences.” Hacking, Ian. The Social
Construction of What? 1999. Harvard University Press. P. 94.
“Hilary Putnam hit the nail on the head, when he wrote about a ‘common
philosophical error of supposing that ‘reality’ must refer to a single
super thing, instead of looking at the ways in which we endlessly
renegotiate–and are forced to renegotiate–our notion of reality as our
language and our life develops.’” Hacking, Ian. The Social Construction of
What? 1999. Harvard University Press. P. 101. Reference is to Putnam,
Hilary. 1994. “Sense, nonsense and the senses: An inquiry into the powers
of the human mind.” The Journal of Philosophy. 91:445-517. P. 452.
“One of the reasons that I dislike talk of social construction is that it
is like a miasma, a curling mist within which hover will-o’-the-wisps
luring us to destruction. Yet such talk will no more go away than will our
penchant for talking about reality. There are deep-seated needs for both
ideas.” Hacking, Ian. The Social Construction of What? 1999. Harvard
University Press. P. 101.
“... a cardinal difference between the traditional natural and social
sciences is that the classifications employed in the natural sciences are
indifferent kinds, while those employed in the social sciences are mostly
interactive kinds.” Hacking, Ian. The Social Construction of What? 1999.
Harvard University Press. P. 108.
“In the end, the ‘real vs construction’ tension turns out to be a
relatively minor technical matter. How to devise a plausible semantics for
a problematic class of kind terms? Terms for interactive kinds apply to
human beings and their behavior. They interact with the people classified
by them. They are kind-terms that exhibit a looping effect, that is, that
have to be revised because the people classified in a certain way change
in response to being classified. On the other hand, some of these
interactive kinds may pick out genuine causal properties, biological
kinds, which, like all indifferent kinds, are unaffected, as kinds, by
what we know about them. The semantics of Kripke and Putnam can be used to
give a formal gloss to this phenomenon.
“Far more decisive than semantics is the dynamics of interactive kinds.
The vast bulk of constructionist writing has examined the dynamics of this
or that classification and the human beings that are classified by it.”
Hacking, Ian. The Social Construction of What? 1999. Harvard University
Press. P. 123.
“A precondition for reasoning, in a community, is that by and large
classifications are in place and shared, although they can also always be
invented and modified. The selection and organization of kinds determines,
according to Goodman, what we call the world ...” Hacking, Ian. The Social
Construction of What? 1999. Harvard University Press. P. 129. Reference is
to Goodman, Nelson. 1978. Ways of Worldmaking. Hackett.
“Some metaphors do not catch on. Thus the metaphor of the nutritionally
battered child, proposed by the Indian pediatrician to describe
malnourished children in the subcontinent and elsewhere, fell by the
wayside. This metaphor was not fueled by the deep passions of innocence,
incest, and the collapse of nuclear family; it was just millions of hungry
children of no significance.
“Child abuse served as a cutting-edge metaphor closer to its home. With
its ramifications in sex, beating, and emotions, it does not pick out one
kind of behavior. It is a kind whose power is to collect many different
kinds, often by metaphor. This power can be put to use by many an
interested party. At the time of the 1990 Gulf War the spokesman for the
Kuwaiti government in exile stated for television viewers of the West that
his country was a small, abused, and molested child. A man in Charleston,
West Virginia, unhappy with the way his town was planting trees in the
sidewalk growled, ‘We have child abuse–this is tree abuse!’ and founded a
Society for the Prevention of Cruelty to Trees.
“That is a bad joke. Missing children are not. But they too represent a
cause that uses child abuse as a metaphor. The advertisements for ‘missing
children’ that in the early 1980s plastered American cereal packages,
chocolate bars, milk cartons, and other family artifacts, not to mention
direct mail and posters at laundromats and bus stations, were presented as
trying to save victims of child abuse. In fact a large proportion of the
advertised missing children arose from custody disputes....”
“‘Child abuse’ is a potent metaphor because it has the property of
instantly concealing its use as metaphor. Once something is labeled child
abuse, you are not supposed to say, wait a minute, that is stretching
things. Which labels stick depends less on their intrinsic merits than on
the network of interested parties that wish to attach these labels.”
Hacking, Ian. The Social Construction of What? 1999. Harvard University
Press. Pp. 151-2.
“The idea [“strong thesis of symmetry”] is that an explanation of why a
group of investigators holds true beliefs should have a very similar
structure to an explanation of why another group holds false beliefs.”
Hacking, Ian. The Social Construction of What? 1999. Harvard University
Press. P. 202.
Authors & Works
cited in this section:
Ball, Philip.
Nature’s Patterns: A Tapestry in Three Parts - Branches.
Barfield, Owen,
Saving the Appearances: A Study of Idolatry
Bateson, Gregory, Mind and Nature; a Necessary Unity
Bateson, Gregory, Steps to an Ecology of Mind
Ben-Menahem, Yemima, ed. Hilary Putnam
Bloom, Allan, The Closing of the American Mind
Brown, Wendy. Politics Out of History
Burling, Robbins. The Talking Ape: How Language Evolved
Collins, Randall. The Sociology of Philosophies: A Global Theo
Corvalis, Romantic poet
Davies, Paul & J. Gribbin. The Matter Myth
Dyson, George. Darwin among the Machines: The Evolution of Global
Intelligence
Evernden, Neil. The Social Creation of Nature
Feynman, Richard. The Feynman Lectures on Physics
Funkenstein, Amos. Theology and the Scientific Imagination Fro
Gardner, James. Biocosm: The New Scientific Theory of Evolution:
Intelligent Life is the Architect of the
Gaukroger, Stephen. Francis Bacon and the Transformation of Early-Modern
Philosophy.
Gellner, Ernest. Plough, Sword and Book: The Structure of Huma
Gellner, Ernest, Postmodernism, Reason and Religion
Gillespie, Michael Allen. The Theological Origins of Modernity
Griffin, David Ray. Unsnarling the World-Knot: Conscioiusness,
Hacking, Ian. The Social Construction of What?
Haraway, Donna J. Simians, Cyborgs, and Women: The Reinvention
Harman, Graham. Prince of Networks: Bruno Latour and Metaphysics.
Hatfield, Gary. “Reason, Nature, and God in Descartes.”
Hite, Shere, The Hite Report; Women and Love; A Cultural Revolu
Kline, Morris, Mathematics: The Loss of Certainty
Kuhn, Thomas, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions
Lanham, Richard. The Economics of Attention: Style and Substance in the
Age of Information
Latour, Bruno. Pandora’s Hope: Essays on the Reality of Scienc
Latour, Bruno. We Have Never Been Modern
Latour, Bruno. Politics of Nature: How to Bring the Sciences into
Democracy
Lewis, C.S. The Discarded Image: An Introduction to Medieval and Ren
Mainzer, Klaus. "Causality in Natural, Technical, and Social Systems."
Miller, James, The Passion of Michel Foucault
Morin, Edgar. Homeland Earth: A Manifesto for a New Millennium
Oyama, Susan. Evolution’s Eye: A Systems View of the Biology-Culture
Pearl, Judea. Causality: Models, Reasoning, and Inference.
Pepper, Stephen C., World Hypotheses
Rockwell, W. Teed. Neither Brain nor Ghost: A Nondualist Alter
Sattler, Rolf. Bio-Philosophy
Sawyer, R. Keith. Social Emergence: Societies as Complex Systems
Schlagel, Richard H., Contextual Realism; A Meta-physical Frame
Snell, Bruno. The Discovery of the Mind in Greek Philosophy an
Tarnas, Richard, The Passion of the Western Mind
Taylor, Mark C. The Moment of Complexity: Emerging Network Culture
Thompson, William I. Natural Drift and the Evolution of Culture
Tuck, Richard. Hobbes: A Very Short Introduction.
Ulanowicz, Robert. A Third Window: Natural Life beyond Newton and Darwin
Wallerstein, Immanuel. World-Systems Analysis: An Introduction
Wimsatt, William. Re-Engineering Philosophy for Limited Beings: Piecewise
Approximations