Citations related to MIND (Philosophy of ...)
and to WHAT IS KNOWING
(works cited listed at bottom):
"The tale of the tuna reminds us that biological systems profit profoundly
from local environmental structure. The environment is not best conceived
solely as a problem domain to be negotiated. It is equally, and crucially,
a resource to be factored into the solutions. This simple observation has,
as we have seen, some far-reaching consequences.
"First and foremost, we must recognize the brain for what it is. Ours are
not the brains of disembodied spirits conveniently glued into ambulant,
corporeal shells of flesh and blood. Rather, they are essentially the
brains of embodied agents capable of creating and exploiting structure in
the world. Conceived as controllers of embodied action, brains will
sometimes devote considerable energy not to the direct, one-stop solution
of a problem, but to the control and exploitation of environmental
structures. Such structures, molded by an iterated sequence of brain-world
interactions, can alter and transform the original problem until it takes
a form that can be managed with the limited resources of
pattern-completing, neural-network-style cognition.
"Second, we should therefore beware of mistaking the problem-solving
profile of the embodied, socially and environmentally embedded mind for
that of the basic brain. Just because humans can do logic and science, we
should not assume that the brain contains a full-blown logic engine or
that it encodes scientific theories in ways akin to their standard
expression in words and sentences. Instead, both logic and science rely
heavily on the use and manipulation of external media, especially the
formalisms of language and logic and the capacities of storage,
transmission, and refinement provided by cultural institutions and by the
use of spoken and written text. These resources, I have argued, are best
seen as alien but complementary to the brain's style of storage and
computation. The brain need not waste its time replicating such
capacities. Rather, it must learn to interface with the external media in
ways that maximally exploit their peculiar virtues.
"Third, we must begin to face up to some rather puzzling (dare I say
metaphysical?) questions. For starters, the nature and the bounds of the
intelligent agent look increasingly fuzzy. Gone is the central executive
in the brain--the real boss who organizes and integrates the activities of
multiple special-purpose subsystems. And gone is the neat boundary between
the thinker (the bodiless intellectual engine) and the thinker's world. In
place of this comforting image we confront a vision of mind as a grab bag
of inner agencies whose computation roles are often best described by
including aspects of the local environment (both in complex control loops
and in a variety of information transformations and manipulations). In
light of all this, it may for some purposes be wise to consider the
intelligent system as a spatio-temporally extended process not limited by
the tenuous envelope of skin and skull. Less dramatically, the traditional
divisions among perception, cognition, and action look increasingly
unhelpful." Clark, Andy, Being There: Putting brain, Body, and World
Together Again, MIT Press, 1997. pp. 220-1.
“Mind and matter are constructs, whereas pure experience, which is neutral
between the two, is primordial. One implication of the hypothesis that we
are directly acquainted with reality is that the contents of consciousness
can no longer be regarded as being ‘in the mind’ (let alone in the brain).
Reality just is the flux of experience.” Wallace, B. Alan. The Taboo of
Subjectivity: Toward a New Science of Consciousness. Oxford University
Press. 2000. p. 63
“Representation implies symbolic activity, an activity that is certainly
at the center of our semantic and syntactical language skills. It is no
wonder that in thinking about how the brain can repeat a performance–that
it can, for example, call up what may appear to be an image already
experienced–we are tempted to say that the brain represents. The flaws in
yielding to this temptation, however, are obvious: There is no precoded
message in the signal, no structures capable of the high-precision storage
of a code, no judge in nature to provide decisions on alternative
patterns, and no homunculus in the head to read a message. For these
reasons, memory in the brain cannot be representation in the same way as
it is in our devices.” Edelman, Gerald and Tononi, Giulio. A Universe of
Consciousness: How Matter becomes Imagination. Basic Books. 2000. p. 94.
“...the key conclusion is that whatever its form, memory itself is a
system property. It cannot be equated exclusively with circuitry, with
synaptic changes, with biochemistry, with value constraints, or with
behavioral dynamics. Instead, it is the dynamic result of the interactions
of all these factors acting together, serving to select an output that
repeats a performance or an act.” Edelman, Gerald and Tononi, Giulio. A
Universe of Consciousness: How Matter becomes Imagination. Basic Books.
2000. p. 99.
"There is no single, definitive 'stream of consciousness,' because there
is no central Headquarters, no Cartesian Theater where 'it all comes
together' for the perusal of a Central Meaner. Instead of such a single
stream (however wide), there are multiple channels in which specialist
circuits try, in parallel pandemoniums, to do their various things,
creating Multiple Drafts as they go. Most of these fragmentary drafts of
'narrative' play short-lived roles in the modulation of current activity
but some get promoted to further functional roles, in swift succession, by
the activity of a virtual machine in the brain. The seriality of this
machine (its 'von Neumannesque' character) is not a 'hard-wired' design
feature, but rather the upshot of a succession of coalitions of these
specialists.
"The basic specialists are part of our animal heritage. They were not
developed to perform peculiarly human actions, such as reading and
writing, but ducking, predator-avoiding, face-recognizing, grasping,
throwing, berry-picking, and other essential tasks. They are often
opportunistically enlisted in new roles, for which their native talents
more or less suit them. The result is not bedlam only because the trends
that are imposed on all this activity are themselves the product of
design. Some of this design is innate, and is shared with other animals.
But it is augmented, and sometimes even overwhelmed in importance, by
microhabits of thought that are developed in the individual, partly
idiosyncratic results of self-exploration and partly the predesigned gifts
of culture. Thousands of memes, mostly borne by language, but also by
wordless 'images' and other data structures, take up residence in an
individual brain, shaping its tendencies and thereby turning it into a
mind." Dennett, Daniel, Consciousness Explained, Little, Brown and
Company, 1991, pps. 253-4.
"The existence of developmental principles leading to variance in
connections and to overlapping arbors with unidentifiable (and not
necessarily repeatable) patterns of synapses creates a crisis for those
who believe that the nervous system is precise and 'hardwired' like a
computer. We may ask 'How has this crisis been met, when it has been
recognized at all, by those who believe in the idea of the brain as a
computer?
"First, these explanations dismiss variations below a certain microscopic
level as 'noise,,' a necessary consequence of the developmental dilemma.
Second, they deal with the absence of uniquely specified connections by
arguing that higher levels of organization such as maps either do not need
such connections or compensate for their absence in some fashion. And
third, they explain the absence of precisely identified synaptic inputs by
assuming that neurons use a code similar to those used to identify phone
credit card or computer users. In neurons, the place and time codes
presumably relate to the frequency, spacing, or type of neuronal
electrical activity, or to the kinds of chemical transmitters with which
they are associated. Notice, however, that these explanations assume that
individual neurons carry information, just as some electronic devices
carry information. I argue later that this is not a defensible assumption
and that these explanations are inadequate. No convincing evidence for the
kinds of codes that humans use in telegraphy, computing, or other forms of
human communication has been found in the human nervous system.
"This brings us to some deeper riddles for those who would propose that the
brain is a kind of computer. These riddles constitute a set of functional
crises pertaining to physiology and to psychology. The first is this: If
one explores the microscopic network of synapses with electrodes to detect
the results of electrical firing, the majority of synapses are not
expressed, that is, they show no detectable firing activity. They are what
have been called 'silent synapses.' But why are they silent, and how does
their silence relate to the signals, codes, or messages that they are
supposed to be carrying?
"A second dilemma concerns the functions and interactions of maps of the
kind we have already considered for the retinotectal system. Despite the
conventional wisdom of anatomy books, these maps are not fixed; in some
brain areas, there are major fluctuations in the borders of maps over
time. Moreover, maps in each different individual appear to be unique.
Most strikingly, the variability of maps in adult animals depends on the
available signal input. This might not seem to pose a dilemma at first;
after all, computers change theirs 'maps' or tables on the alteration of
software. But the functioning maps of the nervous system are based on
anatomical maps--and at this anatomical level, they are changed in the
adult brain only by the death of neurons. If the functioning neural maps
are changing as a result of 'software' changes, what is the code that
gives two different individuals with variant anatomical maps the same
output or result? One standard explanation is to say that there are
alternative systems in the brain that handle changing input, each
alternative fixed and hard-wired but switched in or out by changing input.
The facts show, however, that the variance of neural maps is not discrete
or two-valued but rather continuous, fine-grained, and extensive. Thus,
the number of alternatives would have to be very large.
"Another set of observations brings us to psychological dilemmas of the
most profound kind. They cast doubt on the idea that the complex behavior
of animals with complex brains can be explained solely be 'learning.'
Indeed, this crisis highlights the fundamental problem of neuroscience:
How can an animal initially confront a small number of 'events' or
'objects' and after this exposure adaptively categorize of recognize an
indefinite number of novel objects (even in a variety of contexts) as
being similar or identical to the small set that it first encountered? How
can an animal, in the absence of a teacher, recognize an object at all?
How can it then generalize and 'construct a universal' in the absence of
that object or even in its presence? This kind of generalization occurs
without language in animals such as pigeons, as I discuss later on.
"Explanations of these challenging problems tend either to rely on the
existence of hidden cues, not obvious to the experimenter, or to treat the
world of the responding organism as if its 'objects' or 'events' came with
labels on them. But in reality, the world, with its 'objects,' is an
unlabeled place; the number of ways in which macroscopic boundaries in an
animal's environment can be partitioned by that animal into objects is
very large, if not infinite. Any assignment of boundaries made by an
animal is relative, not absolute, and depends on its adaptive or intended
needs.
"What is striking is that the ability to partition 'objects' and their
arrangements depends on the functioning of the maps that we discussed
earlier. But how do maps interact to give definition of objects and
clear-cut action or behavior? In human beings, a consideration of this
question leads to what I call the homunculus crisis: the unitary
appearance to a perceiver of perceptual processes that are known to be
based on multiple and complex parallel subprocesses and on many maps."
Edelman, Gerald, Bright Air, Brilliant Fire; on the Matter of the Mind,
Basic, 1992, 27-8.
“This unity with our body, however, is no more strict identity than is our
unity with our own past experience. Rather: ‘The body is that portion of
nature with which each moment of human experience intimately cooperates.
There is an inflow and outflow of factors between the bodily actuality and
the human experience, so that each shares in the existence of the other.’
Griffin, David Ray. Unsnarling the World-Knot: Consciousness, Freedom, and
the Mind-Body Problem. University of California Press. 1998. p. 148.
Subquote is from Alfred North Whitehead, Modes of Thought, 1938. p. 115.
"Individuals in possession of reading, writing, and other visuo-graphic
skills thus become somewhat like computers with networking capabilities;
they are equipped to interface, to plug into whatever network becomes
available. And once plugged in, their skills are determined by both the
network and their own biological inheritance. Humans without such skills
are isolated from the external memory system, somewhat like a computer
that lacks the input/output devices needed to link up with a network.
Network codes are collectively held by specified groups of people; those
who possess the code, and the right of access, share a common source of
representations and the knowledge encoded therein. Therefore, they share a
common memory system; and as the data base in that system expands far
beyond the mastery of any single individual, the system becomes by far the
greatest determining factor in the cognitions of individuals.
"The memory system, once collectivized into the external symbolic storage
system, becomes virtually unlimited in capacity and much more robust and
precise. Thought moves from the relatively informal narrative ramblings of
the isolated mind to the collective arena, and ideas thus accumulate over
the centuries until they acquire the precision of continuously refined
exterior devices, of which the prime example is modern science. But
science, ubiquitous though it is at present, is atypical in historical
terms. Human cultural products have usually been stored in less obviously
systematic forms: religions, rituals, oral literary traditions, carvings,
songs–in fact, in any cultural device that allows some form of enduring
externalized memory, with rules and routes of access." Donald, Merlin.
Origins of the Modern Mind. Harvard University Press. 1991. p. 311.
“The need to make a coherent, conscious scene out of seemingly disparate
elements is seen at all levels and in all modalities of consciousness.”
Edelman, Gerald and Tononi, Giulio. A Universe of Consciousness: How
Matter becomes Imagination. Basic Books. 2000. p. 26.
“However, anatomical segregation is only half the story. The other half is
anatomical integration:” Edelman, Gerald and Tononi, Giulio. A Universe of
Consciousness: How Matter becomes Imagination. Basic Books. 2000. p. 44.
“...reentry allows for a unity of perception and behavior that would
otherwise be impossible, given the absence in the brain of a unique,
computerlike central processor with detailed instructions or of
algorithmic calculations for the coordination of functionally segregated
areas.” Edelman, Gerald and Tononi, Giulio. A Universe of Consciousness:
How Matter becomes Imagination. Basic Books. 2000. p. 49.
“In another series of experiments focused on the motor side of
consciousness, Libet showed that the conscious intention to act appears
only after a delay of about 350 msec from the onset of specific cerebral
activity that precedes a voluntary act.” Edelman, Gerald and Tononi,
Giulio. A Universe of Consciousness: How Matter becomes Imagination. Basic
Books. 2000. p. 69.
“The three-way fracturing of the emotion category into socially sustained
pretenses, affect program responses and higher cognitive states extends to
many specific emotion categories, such as anger. Some instances of anger
fall into each of these three categories.” Griffiths, Paul E. What
Emotions Really Are. University of Chicago Press. 1997. p. 17.
"Holding as we do that, while knowledge of any kind is a thing to be
honoured and prized, one kind of it may, either by reason of its greater
exactness or of a higher dignity and greater wonderfulness in its objects,
be more honourable and precious than another, on both accounts we should
naturally be led to place in the front rank the study of the soul. The
knowledge of the soul admittedly contributes greatly to the advance of
truth in general, and, above all, to our understanding of Nature, for the
soul is in some sense the principle of animal life....
"A further problem presented by the affections of soul is this: are they
all affections of the complex of body and soul, or is there any one among
them peculiar to the soul by itself? To determine this is indispensable
but difficult. If we consider the majority of them, there seems to be no
case in which the soul can act or be acted upon without involving the
body, e.g., anger, courage, appetite, and sensation generally. Thinking
seems the most probable exception; but if this too proves to be a form of
imagination or to be impossible without imagination, it too requires a
body as a condition of its existence." Aristotle. Psychology. c. 350 B.C.,
translated by J.A. Smith, from Book I, The Pocket Aristotle. Washington
Square Press. 1958. pp. 50, 52.
“In the twentieth century, scientific materialism was the ideology that
suppressed modes of inquiry into mental phenomena that do not conform to
its principles. Modern science began, with the Copernican Revolution, by
displacing humanity from the center of the natural world, but scientific
materialism has gone to the extreme of denying human subjectiviy any place
at all in the natural world. This dogma would rather deny the existence of
introspection, or at least marginalize its significance, than acknowledge
that, four hundred years after the Scientific Revolution, we still have no
scientific means of exploring consciousness directly. In this regard, we
are right now in a dark age; but the extent of our ignorance of mental
phenomena is obscured by the extraordinary progress that has been made in
the physical sciences, including modern neuroscience.” The Taboo of
Subjectivity: Toward a New Science of Consciousness. B. Alan Wallace.
Oxford University Press. 2000. p. 88
“After four centuries of advances in scientific knowledge, more than a
century of psychological research, and roughly a half century of progress
in the neurosciences, even most advocates of scientism acknowledge that
science has yet to give any intelligible account of the nature of
consciousness. Nevertheless, the extent of our ignorance concerning
consciousness is often overlooked. This ignorance is like a retinal blind
spot in the scientific vision of the world, of which modern society seems
largely unaware.” The Taboo of Subjectivity: Toward a New Science of
Consciousness. B. Alan Wallace. Oxford University Press. 2000. p. 145.
“However, we emphatically do not identify consciousness in its full range
as arising solely in the brain, since we believe that higher brain
functions require interactions both with the world and with other
persons.” Edelman, Gerald and Tononi, Giulio. A Universe of Consciousness:
How Matter becomes Imagination. Basic Books. 2000. p. xii.
"Regular vigilance gradually turned into regular exploration, and a new
behavioral strategy began to evolve; the strategy of acquiring information
'for its own sake,' just in case it might prove valuable someday. Most
mammals were attracted to this strategy, especially primates, who
developed highly mobile eyes, which, via saccades, provided almost
uninterrupted scanning of the world. This marked a rather fundamental
shift in the economy of the organisms that made this leap: the birth of
curiosity, or epistemic hunger. Instead of gathering information only on a
pay-as-you-go, use-it-immediately basis, they began to become what the
psychologist George Miller has called informavores: organisms hungry for
further information about the world they inhabited (and about themselves).
Consciousness Explained, Daniel Dennett, Little, Brown and Company, 1991,
pps. 180-1.
“... we will see not only that biological and mental processes are
isomorphic but that, when taken together, they constitute yet another
complex adaptive system.” Taylor, Mark C. The Moment of Complexity:
Emerging Network Culture. University of Chicago. 2001. p. 206.
[Claim of] “Strong continuity: Life and mind have a common abstract
pattern. The functional properties characteristic of mind are enriched
versions of the functional properties that are fundamental to life in
general.” Godfrey-Smith, Peter. Complexity and the Function of Mind in
Nature. Cambridge University Press. 1996. p. 73.
“...the understanding of intentionality and causality requires the
individual to understand the mediating forces in these external events
that explain ‘why’ a particular antecedent-consequent sequence occurs as
it does–and these mediating forces are typically not readily observable.”
Tomasello, Michael. The Cultural Origins of Human Cognition. Harvard
University Press. 1999. p. 23.
“Neurons come in two flavors, excitatory and inhibitory,...” Edelman,
Gerald and Tononi, Giulio. A Universe of Consciousness: How Matter becomes
Imagination. Basic Books. 2000. p. 40.
“The afflictions of the mind are naturally calmed when the mind is settled
in a state of nongrasping, and the clear and empty nature of awaeness is
vividly perceived. Whenever thoughts arise, one simply observes them
without aversion or approval, and by so doing, thoughts no longer impede
the cultivation of sustained attention, nor do they obscure the nature of
consciousness. This practice is sometimes elucidated with the analogy of a
raven at sea. According to ancient Indian tradition, when a ship went out
to sea, a raven was brought along; and when the navigator wanted to know
whether he had come near shore, he would release the raven. As in the
biblical account of Noah and the ark, if there was no land nearby, the
raven would circle around and around, and eventually alight back on the
ship. Likewise, in this contemplative practice, one releases the mind so
that thoughts flow out freely, without suppressing any of them. As long as
thoughts are arising, one observes them without interference, and
eventually they disappear, or ‘alight’ back in the nature of awareness
from which they originated. With sustained practice, without ever
suppressing ideation, the mind becomes still and conceptual dispersion
ceases of its own accord.” The Taboo of Subjectivity: Toward a New Science
of Consciousness. B. Alan Wallace. Oxford University Press. 2000. p. 111.
“While there are valid and invalid cognitions, there are no valid and
invalid brain states, any more than there are meaningful and meaningless
brain states.” The Taboo of Subjectivity: Toward a New Science of
Consciousness. B. Alan Wallace. Oxford University Press. 2000. p. 132.
“The noosphere is a product of the biosphere as transformed by human
knowledge and action.”
“The noosphere represents an ultimate and inevitable sphere of evolution.”
“The noosphere is a manifestation of global mind.”
“The noosphere is the mental sphere in which change and creativity are
inherent although essentially unpredictable.” Samson, Paul and David Pitt.
The Biosphere and Noosphere Reader. Routledge. 1999. Pps. 2-3.
“We should then be proceeding precisely on the lines of Copernicus’
primary hypothesis. Failing of satisfactory progress in explaining the
movements of the heavenly bodies on the supposition that they all revolved
round the spectator, he tried whether he might not have better success if
he made the spectator to revolve and the stars to remain at rest. A
similar experiment can be tried in metaphysics, as regards the intuition
of objects. If intuition must conform to the constitution of the objects,
I do not see how we could know anything of the latter a priori; but if the
object (as object of the senses) must conform to the constitution of our
faculty of intuition, I have no difficulty in conceiving such a
possibility.” Jay Ogilvy’s quote from Kant, I., Preface to the Critique of
Pure Reason, on page 25-6 of his “Coming Together” article from CTR
conference on evolution and consciousness (Preface to the Second Edition,
p. 22 (B xvi-xvii); tr. Norman Kemp Smith, St. Martin’s Press, New York,
1961.
“...the key conclusion is that whatever its form, memory itself is a
system property. It cannot be equated exclusively with circuitry, with
synaptiic changes, with biochemistry, with value constraints, or with
behavioral dynamics. Instead, it is the dynamic result of the interactions
of all these factors acting together, serving to select an output that
repeats a performance or an act.” Edelman, Gerald & Tononi, Giulio. A
Universe of Consciousness: How Matter Becomes Imagination. Basic Books.
2000. P. 99.
"The view we advocate here is reflected by a growing body of research in
cognitive science. In areas as diverse as the theory of situated cognition
(Suchman 1987), studies of real-world-robotics (Beer 1989), dynamical
approaches to child development (Thelen and Smith 1994), and research on
the cognitive properties of collectives of agents (Hutchins 1995),
cognition is often taken to be continuous with processes in the
environment." Clark, Andy & Chalmers, David. "The Extended Mind." Analysis
58.1 January 1998. p. 10.
“Figure and ground are aspects of human cognition. They are not features
of objective, mind-independent reality.” Johnson, Mark & George Lakoff.
Philosophy in the Flesh: The Embodied Mind and Its Challenge to Western
Thought. Basic Books. 1999. P. 198.
“The structure of concepts includes prototypes of various sorts: typical
cases, ideal cases, social stereotypes, salient exemplars, cognitive
reference points, end points of graded scales, nightmare cases, and so on.
Each type of prototype uses a distinct form of reasoning. Most concepts
are not characterized by necessary and sufficient conditions.” Johnson,
Mark & George Lakoff. Philosophy in the Flesh: The Embodied Mind and Its
Challenge to Western Thought. Basic Books. 1999. P. 77.
“Up to about eight months of age, infants interact with the world,
including other people, largely in terms of what Piaget called sensori-motor
schemata. They are engaged in developing motor skills and the knowledge
that comes with them–they move limbs, grasp and manipulate objects and use
objects in conjunction with one other, as when repeatedly banging on a
surface with a spoon. Then, what Tomasello calls the nine-month revolution
occurs. Infants begin to engage with objects and other people in the form
of a triad–self, other and object–where previously all interactions were
dyadic, involving self and other or self and object.” Plotkin, Henry. The
Imagined World Made Real: Towards a Natural Science of Culture. Rutgers
University Press. 2003. P. 198.
“... over the last twenty years a number of views of mental representation
have been developed that break from the encoding tradition. One of these
is the notion of distributed representation. On this view of
representation, what is in the head are not discrete symbols, each
encoding their own piece of information, but less content-laden nodes
which, in combination with the connection strengths linking them,
collectively represent information about the world. A related alternative
conception of representation is that of subsymbolic computation, whereby
the units over which the computations are defined, the representations,
are not themselves symbols (that is, codes). Both of these conceptions of
representation were developed within a connectionist framework, but they
have a basis in dynamic approaches to cognition more generally. What these
views share is the idea of thinking about representation as fleeting,
situated, dynamic, and interactive, and as such they mark a departure from
encoding views of representation.” Wilson, Robert A. Boundaries of the
Mind: The Individual in the Fragile Sciences. Cambridge University Press.
2004. P. 148.
“Representation is not simply a form of encoding but more generally a form
of informational exploitation of which encoding is a special case.
Representations need not be thought of as internal copies of or codes for
worldly structures. Rather, representation is an activity that individuals
perform in extracting and deploying information that is used in their
further actions.” Wilson, Robert A. Boundaries of the Mind: The Individual
in the Fragile Sciences. Cambridge University Press. 2004. P. 183.
“This idea [mediational approach to development] carried with it the
working assumption that individual mental abilities are significantly
modified by the various mediational tools that they employ. Such mediators
include maps, tools, and other artifacts, numerical systems, memory aids,
and, most importantly for Vygotsky, spoken and written language. All such
mediators are not only cultural products in that they are the products of
particular cultural histories and thus are available to an individual only
within the corresponding cultural contexts. In addition, they are employed
primarily within the context of social interaction and facilitation,
typically in small groups or dyads. As Vygotsky says, ‘The path from
object to child and from child to object passes through another person.
This complex human structure is the product of a developmental process
deeply rooted in the links between individual and social history.’”
Wilson, Robert A. Boundaries of the Mind: The Individual in the Fragile
Sciences. Cambridge University Press. 2004. Pps. 200-1.
“Although I have said less about the mind as embodied, I think that the
exploitative view of representation can be applied to make sense of the
embodiment of cognition as well, where the body becomes another resource
that cognitive systems use to work their magic no different in kind from
cognitive resources in the environment to which the individual is
coupled.” Wilson, Robert A. Boundaries of the Mind: The Individual in the
Fragile Sciences. Cambridge University Press. 2004. P. 210.
“The externalism developed in this chapter takes the symbolic nature of
thought seriously but suggests that internal symbols are simply one kind
of cognitive resource used in memory (as constituents of a store-house),
[in] cognitive development (as constituents of theories), and in folk
psychology (as consituents of beliefs). External symbols are an obvious
second kind of cognitive resource used in cognitive processing, but simply
to see externalists as adding external to internal symbols would be to
mischaracterize the shift in perspective implied by the externalism I have
defended. For the central notion becomes that of a cognitive system. Some
cognitive systems are wide, and some contain both internal and external
symbols. But enactive, bodily cognitive systems, such as wide procedural
memory systems, may be conceptualized in terms of explicit symbols only
with some strain, as may wide perceptual systems that involve the
extraction of information that is usually thought of as non- or
sybsymbolic.
“A large part of the significance of mind-world coupling lies in its
iterative nature. We take part of the world, and learn how to incorporate
and use it as part of our cognitive processing. That, in turn, allows us
to integrate other parts of the world that, in turn, both boost our
cognitive capacities and allow us to cognitively integrate further parts
of the world. And so on. Although some recent discussions of the
embeddedness of cognition have focused on novel and future
technologies–from cell phones, to electronic implants, to telerobotics–the
two most significant forms of iterative scaffolding are older than the
human species: the advent of spoken language (itself a scaffold for much
higher cognition and written symbol systems), and the cognitive dependence
of infants on their parents (the mother of all inventions?).” Wilson,
Robert A. Boundaries of the Mind: The Individual in the Fragile Sciences.
Cambridge University Press. 2004. P. 212.
“I shall suggest that processes of awareness call out for a radical
rethinking along externalist lines, one that turns on taking locational
externalism about consciousness more seriously than it has been taken,
even by externalists about the phenomenal. The argument here will be
similar to that given in the previous chapter, where I argued that our
conceptions of memory, cognitive development, and folk psychology should
be explicitly refashioned along externalist lines. At the heart of this
reconceptualization are three features of processes of awareness that have
usually been ignored or downplayed: They are temporally extended; they are
typically scaffolded on environmental and cultural tools; and they are
both embodied and embedded.” Wilson, Robert A. Boundaries of the Mind: The
Individual in the Fragile Sciences. Cambridge University Press. 2004. P.
217.
“Both culturally and individually we construct perception-action cycles
that involve attuning ourselves to the world, and the world to ourselves.
Many such cycles are constituted primarily by conscious experiences and
acts, and their temporal extension, over minutes or hours, goes
hand-in-hand with their spatial extension beyond the brain of individual
cognizers.” Wilson, Robert A. Boundaries of the Mind: The Individual in
the Fragile Sciences. Cambridge University Press. 2004. P. 218.
“The one thing that seems to have united psychologists, neuroscientists,
and cognitive scientists is the assumption that the brain functions to
construct and utilize representations of the world around us. The
ecological psychology promoted here does not share this assumption, and
instead tries to understand how organisms make their way in the world, not
how a world is made inside of organisms.” Reed, Edward S. Encountering the
World: Toward an Ecological Psychology. 1996. Oxford University Press. Pps.
10-11.
“The result of these tendencies is that psychology is divided into a set
of post-Cartesian dualisms: sensation versus perception, stimulus-response
versus cognitive, innate versus learned, reactive versus motivated. These
dualisms reinforce the belief that reactive behavior is relatively
unvarying and mechanistic, whereas instructed behavior is flexible–but
they do this simply by way of assumption, not by way of testing or
verifying such claims. In turn, these dualisms lead to the idea that the
role of the mind is to make some sort of mental model of the world with
which to ‘interpret’ input signals and create instructions for action. And
this idea firmly places the mind outside the natural world.” Reed, Edward
S. 1996. Encountering the World: Toward an Ecological Psychology. Oxford
University Press. P. 16.
“It is now believed that during the long evolution of our brain, nervous
systems changed in four principal ways. First, they became increasingly
centralized in architecture, evolving from a loose network of nerve cells
(as in the jellyfish) to a spinal column and complex brain with impressive
swellings at the hindbrain and forebrain. This increasingly centralized
structure also became increasingly hierarchical. It appears that newer
additions to the human brain took over control from the previous additions
and in effect became their new masters. Accordingly, the initiation of
voluntary behavior as well as the ability to plan, engage in conscious
thought, and use language depend on neocortical structures. Indeed, the
human neocortex can actually destroy itself if it wishes, as when a
severely depressed individual uses a gun to put a bullet through his or
her skull.”
“Second, there was trend toward encephelization, that is, a concentration
of neurons and sense organs at one end of the organism. By concentrating
neural and sensory equipment in one general location, transmission time
from sense organs to brain was minimized. Third, the size, number, and
variety of elements of the brain increased. Finally, there was an increase
in plasticity, that is, the brain’s ability to modify itself as a result
of experience to make memory and the learning of new perceptual and motor
abilities possible.” Cziko, Gary. Without Miracles: Universal Selection
Theory and the Second Darwinian Revolution. 1995. MIT Press. Pps. 54-5.
"Ekmman, Friesen, and another colleague, Robert Levenson decided to try to
document this effect. They gathered a group of volunteers and hooked them
up to monitors measuring their heart rate and body temperature -- the
physiological signals of such emotions as anger, sadness, and fear. Half
of the volunteers were told to try to remember and relive a particularly
stressful experience. The other half were simply shown how to create, on
their faces, the expressions that corresponded to stressful emotions, such
as anger, sadness, and fear. The second group, the people who were acting,
showed the same physiological responses, the same heightened heart rate
and body temperature, as the first group."
"A few years later, a German team of psychologists conducted a similar
study. They had a group of subjects look at cartoons, either while holding
a pen between their lips -- an action that made it impossible to contract
either of the two major smiling muscles, the risorius and the zygomatic
major -- or while holding a pen clenched between their teeth, which had
the opposite effect and forced them to smile. The people with the pen
between their teeth found the cartoons much funnier. These findings may be
hard to believe, because we take it as a given that first we experience an
emotion, and then we may -- or may not -- express that emotion on our
face. We think of the face as the residue of emotion. What this research
showed, though, is that the process works in the opposite direction as
well. Emotion can also start on the face. The face is not a secondary
billboard for our internal feelings. It is an equal partner in the
emotional process." Gladwell, Malcolm. Blink: The Power of Thinking
Without Thinking. 2005. Little, Brown and Co. Pp. 207-8.
“... the fact of multiple realizability guarantees that the physical story
cannot be the whole story.” Rockwell, W. Teed. Neither Brain nor Ghost: A
Nondualist Alternative to the Mind-Brain Identity Theory. 2005. MIT Press.
P. 4.
“Descartes believed that the soul contacted the body through the brain.
Cartesian materialists made only a relatively slight modification to this
position by saying the soul is the brain. For Descartes, the brain was the
turnstile that knowledge had to pass through to get to the soul; for the
Cartesian materialists the brain was knowledge’s final resting place. Both
positions, however, were lumbered with the same doomed epistemological
question: ‘How does the world get into the brain?’ The only answer
available, given these presuppositions, is ‘a piece at a time, by means of
sense data that are carried through the body to the brain by means of
message cables.’ On closer inspection, even this answer doesn’t really
work. The world itself does not get into the brain, only an impression or
copy of the world. We thus are compelled to accept idealism, and conclude
that we never get to see the real world, only a world of appearances. This
position is so irritatingly counterintuitive that it is eventually
rejected even when no one can find any good arguments against it.”
Rockwell, W. Teed. 2005. Neither Brain nor Ghost: A Nondualist Alternative
to the Mind-Brain Identity Theory. MIT Press. P. 84.
“To understand the alternative I am proposing, it is essential to remember
that this is not the way I am using the word ‘environment.’ Environment,
as I have defined it, is not mind independent. Its borders and qualities
are constituted by its relationship to the mind (goals, projects,
functions) of the organism that dwells in that environment. My alternative
to these two positions might be called a theory of middle-sized content,
because I claim that intentional content supervenes on the environment,
the umwelt, of the thinker or the speaker, and not on either the isolated
brain or on mind-independent reality.” Rockwell, W. Teed. 2005. Neither
Brain nor Ghost: A Nondualist Alternative to the Mind-Brain Identity
Theory. MIT Press. P. 93.
“If Dewey is right, experience is not the sort of thing that can enter the
brain in the form of sense data. Instead, it is constituted by
neurological activity that interacts with extraneurological factors to
create what Millikan calls intentional icons. For language-using
creatures, some of these intentional icons acquire a flexibility in
multitasking that prompts Millikan to call them fact-icons. Words and/or
sentences are clearly the prototypical fact-icons, and perhaps there are
others. But the important point for our purposes is that intentional icons
are constituted by their relationship to the environment even more than
fact-icons are. Fact-icons, by definition, have some measure of
independence from each of the various organism-environment relationships
that they participate in. Intentional icons are far more closely bound up
with a single relatively reflexive body-world relationship. Consequently,
there is far less reason with intentional icons to privilege some
partricular activity in the skull as being somehow distinct and
independent from the rest of the causal nexus that embodies that
relationship.
“The paradigmatic example of an intentional icon is the neurological
activity triggered by the light stimulus that causes a frog to extend its
tongue when it ‘sees’ a fly.” Rockwell, W. Teed. 2005. Neither Brain nor
Ghost: A Nondualist Alternative to the Mind-Brain Identity Theory. MIT
Press. P. 98.
“At any given time, there is a region within my world in which I am
engaged with my tools; the region within which everything is ready-to-hand
for me and thus not observable. And this region, I maintain, is me in the
most unambiguous sense possible. The pattern of activity that occurs
within that region is primarily what embodies me: it includes, but is not
limited to, the activity in my brain and body. When I observe something,
or relate to it in any other way, it becomes part of that region of
activity, and thus, in a nontrivial sense, part of me.” Rockwell, W. Teed.
2005. Neither Brain nor Ghost: A Nondualist Alternative to the Mind-Brain
Identity Theory. MIT Press. Pp. 106-7.
“To determine what we know and what we don’t, we have to separate the
subjective from what can be communicated in what Sellars calls the ‘space
of reasons.’ If we can’t tell the difference between the subjective and
the verbally expressible, it would be impossible to communicate to other
conscious beings. The primary purpose of the concept of the subjective is
to aid us in making this distinction...” Rockwell, W. Teed. 2005. Neither
Brain nor Ghost: A Nondualist Alternative to the Mind-Brain Identity
Theory. MIT Press. P. 121. Subquote is Wilfrid Sellars, 1963, “Empiricism
and the Philosophy of Mind” from Science, Perception, and Reality.
“Searle specifically says, ‘in order to have one belief or desire, I have
to have a whole network of other beliefs and desires.’ This means that he
must also reject the existence of intrinsic properties. If we assume that
at least some of our beliefs express facts about the world, then there
must be a similar relationship that exists between those facts, that is,
in order for one fact to be true, a network of other facts must also be
true, and no one fact can be intrinsically true in and of itself.”
Rockwell, W. Teed. 2005. Neither Brain nor Ghost: A Nondualist Alternative
to the Mind-Brain Identity Theory. MIT Press. Pp. 143-4. Subquote is from
John Searle, 1992, The Rediscovery of the Mind, MIT Press, P. 176.
“The belief in the uniquely intrinsic quality of physical properties can
only be justified by saying something like 'When everyone else talks about
the world, the concepts that they use are dependent on their goals and
purposes. But when physicists talk about the world, their concepts touch
reality itself, unsullied by any goals or provincial perspective.’ There
is simply no reason to privilege the discourse of physicists in this
manner. Physics like any other human activity, requires dividing the world
up into categories that enable the goals of that activity to be achieved.
If you want to track the behavior of the planets, or predict how light
will disperse, there is no other set of concepts that you can use and
still achieve those goals with maximum effectiveness. But that does not
grant intrinsicness to these concepts, any more than the fact that the
concept of heart is necessary to zoology makes the concept of heart
intrinsic.” Rockwell, W. Teed. 2005. Neither Brain nor Ghost: A Nondualist
Alternative to the Mind-Brain Identity Theory. MIT Press. Pp. 144-5.
“We Deweyans claim that even the so-called physical stance is a point of
view that we take because it frequently serves our purposes to do so, and
therefore the physical stance is less ontologically fundamental than the
intentional stance.” Rockwell, W. Teed. 2005. Neither Brain nor Ghost: A
Nondualist Alternative to the Mind-Brain Identity Theory. MIT Press. P.
154.
“Dewey is saying that rather than dividing experience up into a stimulus
and a response, we should think of the reflex arc as being a continuous
circle. It becomes divided into stimulus and response only when we are
thinking about it, not when we are experiencing it.” Rockwell, W. Teed.
2005. Neither Brain nor Ghost: A Nondualist Alternative to the Mind-Brain
Identity Theory. MIT Press. P. 179.
“Reality, Dewey claimed, was fundamentally a continuity, and most
philosophical problems arise from artificially dividing this continuity
into absolute dualisms. Stimulus and response, mind and matter, subject
matter and method, are but moments in a flux that we define only by their
relationship to each other within that flux.” Rockwell, W. Teed. 2005.
Neither Brain nor Ghost: A Nondualist Alternative to the Mind-Brain
Identity Theory. MIT Press. P. 180.
“Consequently, it seems sensible to conclude that the supervenience base
for all mental events, including subjective experiences, includes not only
brain events, but events in the rest of the body and in those parts of the
environment with which the conscious organism maintains a synergetic
relationship. At any given moment, there will be a distinction between
those processes that constitute the subject and those that constitute the
environment. But there is good reason to think that this distinction does
not have a constant and enduring borderline.” Rockwell, W. Teed. 2005.
Neither Brain nor Ghost: A Nondualist Alternative to the Mind-Brain
Identity Theory. MIT Press. P. 206.
“In the four-dimensional universe of space and time, we are confined to a
three-dimensional surface. Only one moment exists in our reality; the
existence of other moments is evident only through the constructs of our
mind. We breathe one lifetime at a time within a thin atmosphere condensed
out of the surrounding sequence of events. All our devices for translating
between sequence and structure serve to extend this atmospheric depth–the
history of life on earth is compressed within sequential strands of DNA;
culture is accumulated in the form of language; somehow our brains
preserve the sequence of our lives from one moment to the next. As far as
we know mind and intelligence exist on an open-ended scale. Perhaps mind
is a lucky accident that exists only at our particular depth of field,
like some alpine flower that blooms between ten thousand and twelve
thousand feet. Or perhaps there is mind at elevations both above and below
our own.” Dyson, George. Darwin among the Machines: The Evolution of
Global Intelligence. 1997. Perseus Books. P. 217.
“The loop through pen and paper is part of the physical machinery
responsible for the shape of the flow of thoughts and ideas that we take,
nonetheless, to be distinctively those of Richard Feynman [in speaking of
his notes as a theoretical physicist]. It reliably and robustly provides a
functionality which, were it provided by goings-on in the head alone, we
would have no hesitation in designating as part of the cognitive
circuitry. Such considerations of parity, once we put our bioprejudices
aside, reveal the outward loop as a functional part of an extended
cognitive machine. Such body- and world-involving cycles are best
understood, or so I shall argue, as quite literally extending the
machinery of mind out into the world–as building extended cognitive
circuits that are themselves the minimal material bases for important
aspects of human thought and reason. Such cycles supersize the mind.”
Clark, Andy. Supersizing the Mind: Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive
Extension. 2008. Oxford University Press. Pp. xxv-xxvi.
“Once the body itself is ‘equipped’ with the right kind of passive
dynamics, powered walking can be brought about in a remarkably elegant and
energy-efficient way. In essence, the tasks of actuation and control have
now been massively reconfigured so that powered, directed locomotion can
come about by systematically pushing, damping, and tweaking a system in
which passive-dynamic effects still play a major role.” Clark, Andy.
Supersizing the Mind: Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive Extension. 2008.
Oxford University Press. P. 5.
“The ‘matching’ of sensors, morphology, motor system, materials,
controller, and ecological niche yields a spread of responsibility for
efficient adaptive response in which ‘not all the processing is performed
by the brain, but certain aspects of it are taken over by the morphology,
materials, and environment [yielding] a ‘balance’ or task-distribution
between the different aspects of an embodied agent’. In such cases, the
details of embodiment may take over some of the work that would otherwise
need to be done by the brain or the neural network controller, an effect
that Pfeifer and Bongard aptly describe as ‘morphological computation.’”
Clark, Andy. Supersizing the Mind: Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive
Extension. 2008. Oxford University Press. P. 7. Subquote is from Pfeifer,
R. and J. Bongard. 2007. How the body shapes the way we think. MIT Press.
P. 100.
“Nontrivial causal spread occurs whenever something we might have expected
to be achieved by a certain well-demarcated system turns out to involve
the exploitation of more far-flung factors and forces.” Clark, Andy.
Supersizing the Mind: Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive Extension. 2008.
Oxford University Press. P. 7.
“As Ballard et al. comment, ‘Changing gaze is analogous to changing the
memory reference in a silicon computer’. (These uses of fixation are thus
described using the term ‘deictic pointers.’)” Clark, Andy. Supersizing
the Mind: Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive Extension. 2008. Oxford
University Press. P. 12. Subquote is from Ballard, Hayhoe, Pook and Rao.
“Deictic codes for the embodiment of cognition.” Behavioral and Brain
Sciences 20:723-767. 1997. P. 725.
“You simply run so that the optical image of the ball appears to present a
straight-line constant speed trajectory against the visual background [in
order to run and catch something like a fly ball]. This solution (the
so-called LOT, for Linear Optical Trajectory, model) exploits a powerful
invariant in the optic flow,...” Clark, Andy. Supersizing the Mind:
Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive Extension. 2008. Oxford University
Press. P. 16.
“Instead of using sensing to get enough information inside, past the
visual bottleneck, so as to allow the reasoning system to ‘throw away the
world’ and solve the problem wholly internally, they use the sensor as an
open conduit allowing environmental magnitudes to exert a constant
influence on behavior. Sensing is here depicted as the opening of a
channel, with successful whole-system behavior emerging when activity in
this channel is kept within a certain range. What is created is thus a
kind of new, task-specific agent-world circuit.” Clark, Andy. Supersizing
the Mind: Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive Extension. 2008. Oxford
University Press. P. 16.
“In work implemented on the famous COG robot, Fitzpatrick and Arsenio show
that the cross-modal binding of incoming signals that display common
rhythmic signatures can aid a robot in learning about objects and, by
including proprioception as a modality, about the nature of its own body.
The robot first detects rhythmic patterns in the individual modalities
(sight, hearing, and proprioception) and then deploys a binding algorithm
to associate signals that display the same kind of periodicity.” Clark,
Andy. Supersizing the Mind: Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive Extension.
2008. Oxford University Press. P. 18. Reference is to Fitzpatrick and
Arsenio. 2004. “Feel the beat: Using cross-modal rhythm to integrate
perception of objects, others, and self.” Proceedings of the fourth
International Workshop on Epigenetic Robotics. From Berthouze, Kozima,
Prince, Sandini, Stojanov, Metta & Balkenius (Eds). Lund University
Cognitive Studies.
“Finally, the active structuring of an information flow is also a potent
between-agent tool, as demonstrated in striking studies by Yu, Ballard,
and Aslin. In these studies, a subject, fitted with eye tracker,
head-mounted camera, microphone, and hand and body trackers describes, as
if to a child (slowly, with clear enunciations) their current actions. The
verbal descriptions, along with the time-locked stream of multimodal
training data recorded by the eye, head, hand, and body trackers, are fed
to an artificial neural network. The task of the network is to learn
visually grounded ‘meaning’ for words for some actions solely by exposure
to the time-locked stream of multimodal training data created by the
active ‘caregiver.’ In the presence of this critical active structuring,
the net can learn image-sound associations using ‘raw’ visual and auditory
data (an unsegmented sound stream and an un-preprocessed video stream) and
without the benefit of any inbuilt ‘language model.’” Clark, Andy.
Supersizing the Mind: Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive Extension. 2008.
Oxford University Press. P. 20. Reference is to Yu, Ballard & Aslin. 2005.
“The role of embodied intention in early lexical acquisition.” Cognitive
Science 29, no. 6: 961-1005.
“We can now formulate the next feature of recent work that I want to
highlight: attention to the possibility that the substrate (the
‘vehicles’) of specific perceptual experiences may involve whole cycles of
world-engaging activity.” Clark, Andy. Supersizing the Mind: Embodiment,
Action, and Cognitive Extension. 2008. Oxford University Press. P. 23.
“Continuous reciprocal causation (CRC) occurs when some system S is both
continuously affecting and simultaneously being affected by activity in
some other system O.” Clark, Andy. Supersizing the Mind: Embodiment,
Action, and Cognitive Extension. 2008. Oxford University Press. P. 24.
The crucial upshot of the emphasis on constant mutual interaction is a
corresponding emphasis on what Van Gelder and Port usefully term total
state. Because we assume that there is widespread and complex
interanimation among multiple system factors, the dynamicist chooses to
focus on changes in total system state over time.” Clark, Andy.
Supersizing the Mind: Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive Extension. 2008.
Oxford University Press. P. 25. Reference is to Van Gelder & Port. “It’s
about time: An overview of the dynamical approach to cognition.” From Mind
as motion: Explorations in the dynamics of cognition. Port and Van Gelder,
Eds. MIT Press. 1995. P. 14.
“Total state explanations do not fare well as a means of understanding
systems in which complex information flow plays a key role.” Clark, Andy.
Supersizing the Mind: Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive Extension. 2008.
Oxford University Press. P. 26.
“The point for present purposes, is that to the extent that neural control
systems exhibit such complex and information-based articulation, the sole
use of total state explanations would tend to obscure explanatorily
important details, such as the various ways in which substate x may vary
independently of substate y and so on.” Clark, Andy. Supersizing the Mind:
Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive Extension. 2008. Oxford University
Press. Pp. 26-7.
“According to Haugeland, the notions of component, system, and interface
are all interdefined and interdefining. Components are those parts of a
larger whole that interact through interfaces. Systems are ‘relatively
independent and self-contained’ composites of such interfaced components.
And an interface itself is ‘a point of interactive ‘contact’ between
components such that the relevant interactions are well-defined, reliable
and relatively simple.” Clark, Andy. Supersizing the Mind: Embodiment,
Action, and Cognitive Extension. 2008. Oxford University Press. P. 32.
Subquotes are from Haugeland. 1998. “Mind embodied and embedded.” From
Having thought: Essays in the metaphysics of mind. Haugeland, J. Ed.
Harvard University Press. P. 213.
“Creatures capable of this kind of deep incorporation of new bodily
structure are examples of what I shall call ‘profoundly embodied agents.’
Such agents are able constantly to negotiate and renegotiate the
agent-world boundary itself.
“Although our own capacity for such renegotiation is, I believe, vastly
underappreciated, it really should come as no great surprise, given the
facts of biological bodily growth and change. The human infant must learn
(by self-exploration) which neural commands bring about which bodily
effects and must then practice until skilled enough to issue those
commands without conscious effort. This process has been dubbed ‘body
babbling’ and continues until the infant body becomes transparent
equipment.” Clark, Andy. Supersizing the Mind: Embodiment, Action, and
Cognitive Extension. 2008. Oxford University Press. Pp. 34-5.
“A quick illustration is provided by recent work on so-called change
blindness. In this work, simple experimental manipulations, involving the
masking of motion transients while various changes are made to a visually
presented scene, reveal the surprising sparseness of the change-specifying
information easily available to conscious reflection. Subjects seldom spot
quite large and important changes, even when the changes are made in focal
vision. Subjects are frequently amazed when they realize just how much has
changed without their noticing it. How should we reconcile the limitations
of such conscious change spotting with out strong sense of rich visual
contact with our surroundings? Part of the answer may be that the strong
feeling of rich visual contact is really a reflection of something
implicit in the larger overall problem-solving organization in which
moment-by-moment vision merely participates. That larger organization
‘assumes’ the (ecologically normal) ability to retrieve, via saccades or
head and body movements, more detailed information as and when needed.
Given such ‘availability on demand,’ we feel that we are fully in command
of the detail.” Clark, Andy. Supersizing the Mind: Embodiment, Action, and
Cognitive Extension. 2008. Oxford University Press. P. 41.
“When, for example, you group your groceries in one bag and mine in
another, or when the cook places washed vegetables in one location and
unwashed ones in another, the effect is to use spatial organization to
simplify problem solving by using spatial proximity to reduce descriptive
complexity. It is intuitive that once descriptive complexity is thus
reduced, processes of selective attention, and of action control, can
operate on elements of a scene that were previously too ‘unmarked’ to
define such operations over. Experience with tags and labels may be a
cheap way of achieving a similar result. Spatial organization reduces
descriptive complexity by means of physical groupings that channel
perception and action toward functional or appearance-based equivalence
classes. Labels allow us to focus attention on all and only the items
belonging to equivalence classes (the red shoes, the gree apples, etc.).
In this way, both linguistic and physical groupings allow selective
attention to dwell on all and only the items belonging to the class. And
the two resources are seen to work in close cooperation. Spatial groupings
are used in teaching children the meanings of words, and mentally
rehearsed words may be used to control activities of spatial grouping.”
“Simple labeling thus functions as a kind of augmented reality trick by
means of which we cheaply and open-endedly project new groupings and
structures onto a perceived scene. Labeling is cheap because it avoids the
physical effort of putting things into piles. And it is open-ended insofar
as it can group in ways that defeat simple spatial display–for example, by
allowing us to selectively attend to the four corners of a tabletop, and
exercise that clearly cannot be performed by physical reorganization!
Linguistic labels, on this view, are tools for grouping and in this sense
act much like real spatial reorganization. But in addition (and unlike
mere physical groupings), they effectively and open-endedly add new
‘virtual’ items (the recalled labels themselves) to the scene. In this
way, experience with tags and labels warps and reconfigures the problem
spaces for the cognitive engine.” Clark, Andy. Supersizing the Mind:
Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive Extension. 2008. Oxford University
Press. Pp. 46-7.
“A vast amount of contemporary human cognitive niche construction likewise
involves the active exploitation of space. David Kirsh, in his classic
treatment ‘The Intelligent Use of Space,’ divides these uses into three
broad and overlapping categories. The first is ‘spatial arrangements that
simplify choice,’ such as laying out cooking ingredients in the order you
will need them or putting your groceries in one bag and mine in another.
The second is ‘spatial arrangements that simplify perception,’ such as
putting the washed mushrooms on the right of the chopping board and the
unwashed ones on the left or the color green dominated jigsaw puzzle
pieces in one pile and the red dominated ones in another. The third is
‘spatial dynamics that simplify internal computation,’ such as repeatedly
reordering the Scrabble pieces so as to prompt better recall of candidate
words or the use of instruments such as slide rules, which transform
arithmetical operations into perceptual alignment activities.” Clark,
Andy. Supersizing the Mind: Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive Extension.
2008. Oxford University Press. Pp. 64-5.
“No other animal uses space as an open-ended cognitive resource,
developing spatial offloadings for new problems on a day-by-day basis.
“It is perhaps noteworthy, then, that the majority of these spatial
arrangement ploys work, as Kirsh himself notes at the end of his long
treatment, by reducing the descriptive complexity of the environment.
Space is often used as a resource for grouping items into equivalence
classes for some purpose (e.g., washed mushrooms, red jigsaw pieces, my
groceries, etc.). It is intuitive that once descriptive complexity is thus
reduced, processes of selective attention, and of action control, can
operate on elements of a scene that were previously too ‘unmarked’ to
define such operations over. Human language is itself notable both for its
open-ended expressive power and for its ability to reduce the descriptive
complexity of the environment. Reduction of descriptive complexity,
however achieved, makes new groupings available for thought and action. In
this way, the intelligent use of space and the intelligent use of language
form a mutually reinforcing pair, pursuing a common cognitive agenda.”
Clark, Andy. Supersizing the Mind: Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive
Extension. 2008. Oxford University Press. P. 65.
“Instead of an innate ‘folk psychology’ module, in the form of a
domain-specific adaptation for ‘mind-reading,’ Sterelny offers a
niche-construction-based account according to which
‘selection for interpretative skills could lead to a different
evolutionary trajectory: selection on parents for actions which scaffold
the development of the interpretative capacities. Selection rebuilds the
epistemic environment to scaffold the development of those capacities.
“Basic perceptual adaptations (e.g., for gaze monitoring, etc.) are thus
supposed to be bootstrapped up to a full-blown mind-reading ability via
the predictable effects of intense social scaffolding: The child is
surrounded by exemplars of mind-reading in action, she is nudged by
cultural inventions such as the use of simplified narratives, prompted by
parental rehearsal of her own intention, and provided with a rich palate
of linguistic tools such as words for mental states.” Clark, Andy.
Supersizing the Mind: Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive Extension. 2008.
Oxford University Press. P. 67. Subquote is from K. Sterelny. Thought in a
Hostile World: The Evolution of Human Cognition. 2003. Blackwell. P. 221.
“Epistemic actions–physical actions that make mental computation easier,
faster or more reliable–are external actions that an agent performs to
change its own computational state.” Kirsh, D., and P. Maglio. “On
distinguishing epistemic from pragmatic action.” Cognitive Science. 18:
513-549. 1994. P. (51)3. Quoted in: Clark, Andy. Supersizing the Mind:
Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive Extension. 2008. Oxford University
Press. P. 71.
“Once we conceive the agent environment relation to be a dynamic one where
agents are causally coupled to their environments at different temporal
frequencies with less or more conscious awareness of the nature of their
active perceptual engagement, we are moving in a direction of seeing
agents more as managers of their interaction, as coordinators locked in a
system of action reaction, rather than as pure agents undertaking actions
and awaiting consequences.” Kirsh, D. “Metacognition, distributed
cognition and visual design.” From Cognition, education and communication
technology. Ed. P. Gardinfors and P. Johansson. Erlbaum. 2004. P. 7.
Quoted in Clark, Andy. Supersizing the Mind: Embodiment, Action, and
Cognitive Extension. 2008. Oxford University Press. P. 73.
“Mental spaces are small conceptual packets constructed as we think and
talk, for purposes of local understanding and action. In the Buddhist monk
network [riddle about whether a monk spending two different whole days
walking up and then down a mountain will be in the same spot at the same
time on both days], we have a mental space for the ascent and another
mental space for the descent. Mental spaces are connected to long-term
schematic knowledge called ‘frames,’ such as the frame of walking along a
path, and to long-term specific knowledge, such as a memory of the time
you climbed Mount Rainier in 2001. The mental space that includes you,
Mount rainier, the year 2001, and your climbing the mountain can be
activated in many different ways and for many different purposes. ‘You
climbed Mount Rainier in 2001' sets up the mental space in order to report
a past event. ‘If you had climbed Mount Rainier in 2001' sets up the same
mental space in order to examine a counterfactural situation and its
consequences. ‘Max believes that you climbed Mount Rainier in 2001' sets
it up again, but now for the purpose of stating what Max believes. ‘Here
is a picture of you climbing Mount Rainier in 2001' evokes the same mental
space in order to talk about the content of the picture. ‘This novel has
you climbing Mount rainier in 2001' reports the author’s inclusion of a
possibly fictional scene in a novel. Mental spaces are very partial. They
contain elements and are typically structured by frames. They are
interconnected, and can be modified as thought and discourse unfold.
Mental spaces can be used generally to model dynamic mappings in thought
and language.” Fauconnier, Gilles & Mark Turner. The Way We Think:
Conceptual Blending and the Mind’s Hidden Complexities. 2002. Basic Books.
P. 40.
“Conceptual integration network. Blends arise in networks of mental
spaces. In the network illustrated in the Basic Diagram, there are four
mental spaces: the two inputs, the generic space, and the blend. This is a
minimal network. Conceptual integration networks can have several input
spaces and even multiple blended spaces.” Fauconnier, Gilles & Mark
Turner. The Way We Think: Conceptual Blending and the Mind’s Hidden
Complexities. 2002. Basic Books. P. 47.
“Emergent structure. Emergent structure arises in the blend that is not
copied there directly from any input. It is generated in three ways:
through composition of projections from the inputs, through completion
based on independently recruited frames and scenarios, and through
elaboration (‘running the blend’).” Fauconnier, Gilles & Mark Turner. The
Way We Think: Conceptual Blending and the Mind’s Hidden Complexities.
2002. Basic Books. P. 48.
“Wide application. Though uniform in their dynamics, integration networks
can serve many different goals. In the examples we have seen so far, these
goals include transfer of emotions (Image Club [Japanese brothel with
school girl theme]) and inferences (Buddhist Monk and Computer Desktop),
counterfactual reasoning (Iron Lady [reasoning about the reaction of US
labor unions in a hypothetical election featuring Maggie Thatcher]),
conceptual change and creativity in science (Complex Numbers), integrated
action (Computer Desktop and Skiing Waiter [ski like a waiter carrying
champagne on a tray above his head]), and construction of identity through
compression (Graduation).” Fauconnier, Gilles & Mark Turner. The Way We
Think: Conceptual Blending and the Mind’s Hidden Complexities. 2002. Basic
Books. Pp. 49-50.
“... a mathematical truth can seem striking and even mysterious, but the
method of proof breaks the mystery down into a sequence of logical steps,
each seemingly simple and obvious, and each leading to the subsequent step
until the conclusion is reached. This was Aristotle’s insight, which also
drives modern computers.
“... this step-by-step understanding is only one side of the coin. The
breaking down of an event into a set of smaller events, each understood
consciously and separately, can paradoxically give us a feeling of less
understanding, because we feel we have not grasped the essential whole. It
is a strength of human understanding to be able to do both, and our
greatest assurance comes when we feel we understand the same event both
ways.” Fauconnier, Gilles & Mark Turner. The Way We Think: Conceptual
Blending and the Mind’s Hidden Complexities. 2002. Basic Books. Pp. 75-6.
“Let us take another look at the Bypass [Poster of three kids dressed as
doctors at an operating table where the message is that we must educate
kids now for medical work later - “Joey, Katie and Todd will be performing
your bypass”]. We have talked generally about cross-space links between
the inputs. The finer-grained structure of these links is extremely
interesting. It includes links from cause to effect, links through time
and through space, links through change, and links through identity. The
input with the children in school and the quality of their education is
causal for the input with doctors of a certain level of competence. This
is a Cause-Effect link between the inputs. There is an interval of at
least a couple of decades between the children and the doctors. This is a
Time link between the inputs. There is a displacement between the physical
space of the schoolroom in one input and the physical space of the
operating room in the other. This is a Space link, where in this instance
we mean physical space. There is a counterpart link between the children
at one stage of life and the doctors later. This is an Identity link. And,
finally, there is a transformation of the children into the doctors. This
is a Change link.
“Blending plays marvelous and imaginative tricks with these links. Look
once more at the blended space in the Bypass. Every one of these
‘outer-space’ links between the inputs to the conceptual integration
network has a compressed counterpart in the blend! There is still
cause-effect in the blend, but now the children must learn all at one
shot. There is still a time interval between now and the surgery, but it
has been compressed from over twenty years into the few minutes between
the time on the clock and the time of the surgery. In the blend, the
schoolroom is the operating room. This is space compression. In the blend,
the children are the doctors. The ‘outer-space’ link of personal Identity
running over thirty years between people whose appearance, experience, and
belief are very different is compressed into what we call ‘uniqueness’ in
the blended space. The ‘outer-space’ protracted change of the youngsters
into employed adults is also compressed in the blend into uniqueness.”
Fauconnier, Gilles & Mark Turner. The Way We Think: Conceptual Blending
and the Mind’s Hidden Complexities. 2002. Basic Books. P. 92.
“Spaces have elements and, often, relations between them. When these
elements and relations are organized as a package that we already know
about, we say that the mental space is framed and we call that
organization a ‘frame.’ So, for example, a mental space in which Julie
purchases coffee at Peet’s coffee shop has individual elements that are
framed by commercial transaction, as well as by the subframe–highly
important for Julie–of buying coffee at Peet’s.” Fauconnier, Gilles & Mark
Turner. The Way We Think: Conceptual Blending and the Mind’s Hidden
Complexities. 2002. Basic Books. P. 102.
“Mental spaces are built up dynamically in working memory, but they can
also become entrenched in long-term memory. For example, frames are
entrenched mental spaces that we can activate all at once. Other kinds of
entrenched mental spaces are Jesus on the Cross, Horatio at the bridge,
and the rings of Saturn. An entrenched mental space typically has other
mental spaces attached to it, in an entrenched way, and they quickly come
along with the activation. Jesus on the Cross evokes the frame of Roman
crucifixion, of Jesus the baby, of Jesus the son of God, of Mary and the
Holy women at the foot of the Cross, of styles of painting the
crucifixion, of moments of the liturgy that refer to it, and many more.
“We will see that entrenchment is a general possibility not just for
individual mental spaces but for networks of spaces. In particular,
integration networks built up dynamically can become entrenched and
available to be activated all at once. Indeed, much of our thinking
consists of activating entrenched integration networks for dealing with
present subjects.
For our present purpose–namely, to characterize sources of variation in
networks–the most pertinent features of mental spaces are the degree of
specificity of the elements, the degree to which they are framed, our
familiarity with the space, the degree to which it is entrenched, and the
degree to which it is tied to our experiences.” Fauconnier, Gilles & Mark
Turner. The Way We Think: Conceptual Blending and the Mind’s Hidden
Complexities. 2002. Basic Books. P. 103.
“A readily available frame of human kinship is the family, which includes
roles for father, mother, child, and so on. This frame prototypically
applies to human beings. Suppose an integration network has one space
containing only this frame, and another space containing only two human
beings, Paul and Sally. When we conceive of Paul as the father of Sally,
we have created a blend in which some of the structure of the family frame
is integrated with the elements Paul and Sally. In the blended space, Paul
is the father of Sally. This is a simplex network. The cross-space mapping
between the input spaces is a Frame-to-values connection–that is, an
organized bundle of role connectors. In this case, the role father
connects to the value Paul and the role daughter connects to the value
Sally.
“In a simplex network, the relevant part of the frame in one input is
projected with its roles, and the elements are projected from the other
input as values of those roles within the blend.” Fauconnier, Gilles &
Mark Turner. The Way We Think: Conceptual Blending and the Mind’s Hidden
Complexities. 2002. Basic Books. P. 120.
“A mirror network is an integration network in which all spaces–inputs,
generic, and blend–share an organizing frame.” Fauconnier, Gilles & Mark
Turner. The Way We Think: Conceptual Blending and the Mind’s Hidden
Complexities. 2002. Basic Books. P. 122.
“A mirror network can integrate many different spaces, provided they share
the same organizing frame. On July 8, 1999, the New York Times reported
that Hicham el-Guerrouj had broken the world record for the mile, with a
time of 3:43:13. An illustration accompanying the article shows a
quarter-mile race-track with six figures running on it, representing el-Guerrouj
in a race against the fastest milers from each decade since Roger
Bannister broke the 4-minute barrier in 1954. El-Guerrouj is crossing the
finish line as Bannister, trailing everyone, is still 120 yards back. This
illustration prompts us to construct a conceptual packet that blends
structure from six separate input mental spaces, each with a 1-mile race
in which the world record is broken by a runner. The blend places all six
runners on a single racetrack, with a single starting time.” Fauconnier,
Gilles & Mark Turner. The Way We Think: Conceptual Blending and the Mind’s
Hidden Complexities. 2002. Basic Books. P. 123.
“Clashes. In a mirror network, there are no clashes between the inputs at
the level of organizing frame, because the frames are the same. But there
will be clashes at more specific levels below the frame level. In Regatta
[news story in 1993 of a catamaran trying to break the 140-year old record
of a clipper sailing from San Francisco to Boston], the centuries and the
kinds of boats in the two spaces clash. In the Buddhist Monk [riddle about
whether a monk spending two different whole days walking up and then down
a mountain will be in the same spot at the same time on both days], the
directions and times of travel in the two spaces clash.” Fauconnier,
Gilles & Mark Turner. The Way We Think: Conceptual Blending and the Mind’s
Hidden Complexities. 2002. Basic Books. P. 125.
“A single-scope network has two input spaces with different organizing
frames, one of which is projected to organize the blend. Its defining
property is that the organizing frame of the blend is an extension of the
organizing frame of one of the inputs but not the other.” Fauconnier,
Gilles & Mark Turner. The Way We Think: Conceptual Blending and the Mind’s
Hidden Complexities. 2002. Basic Books. P. 126.
“Suppose a man tells his older sister about his present troubles, and she
responds,
“‘Do you remember how when you were little you were so intent upon hiding
your treasures that you hid them so well even you could not find them
again? Do you remember that you hid your new penny when you were four and
we never found it? That’s just what you have done with Angela. You’ve been
talking for two hours about all your troubles, but what they boil down to
is that you have hidden away your love for her so deeply that you can’t
see it. Once again, you’ve hidden your penny, even from yourself.’
“This is an example of a single-scope network. The frame that is exploited
in the blend for purposes of understanding is the frame of one input
(hiding the cherished penny too well), and the point of the blend is to
cast light on the other input (the adult brother’s troubled life). Hiding
the Penny is the framing input and the Troubled Life is the focus input.
When there is such a vital relation between the two inputs, the effect of
the network goes far beyond analogy. It adds to the temporal connection in
the overall history a comprehensive pattern of causality.” Fauconnier,
Gilles & Mark Turner. The Way We Think: Conceptual Blending and the Mind’s
Hidden Complexities. 2002. Basic Books. Pp. 127-8.
“A double-scope network has inputs with different (and often clashing)
organizing frames as well as an organizing frame for the blend that
includes parts of each of those frames and has emergent structure of its
own. In such networks, both organizing frames make central contributions
to the blend, and their sharp differences offer the possibility of rich
clashes. Far from blocking the construction of the network, such clashes
offer challenges to the imagination; indeed, the resulting blends can be
highly creative.” Fauconnier, Gilles & Mark Turner. The Way We Think:
Conceptual Blending and the Mind’s Hidden Complexities. 2002. Basic Books.
P. 131.
“Double-scope networks can also operate on strong clashes between the
inputs. Consider the familiar idiomatic metaphor ‘You are digging your own
grave.’ It typically serves as a warning that (1) you are doing bad things
that will cause you to have a very bad experience, and (2) you are unaware
of this causal relation. A conservative parent who keeps his money in his
mattress may express disapproval of an adult child’s investing in the
stock market by saying ‘You are digging your own grave.’
“At first glance, this conventional expression looks like a
straightforward single-scope network, where the organizing frame of
graves, corpses, and burial is projected to organize the blend–a blend in
which someone unwittingly does the wrong things, and ultimately fails.
Failing is being dead and buried; bad moves that precede and cause failure
are digging one’s own grave. It is foolish to bring about one’s own burial
or one’s own failure. And it is foolish not to be aware of one’s own
actions, especially those that may lead to one’s very extinction.
“A closer look, however, reveals that this cannot be a single-scope
network, because in a single-scope network this cross-input mapping aligns
the topologies of the inputs and that topology appears in the blend. But
in Digging Your Own Grave, the topologies of the inputs clash on
causality, intentionality, participant roles, temporal sequence, identity,
and internal event structure. In all these cases, the blend takes its
topology from the ‘unwitting failure’ input, not from the ‘digging the
grave’ input! The causal structure in the blend comes from the ‘unwitting
failure’ input, not the ‘digging the grave’ input. Foolish actions cause
failure, but grave digging does not cause death.” Fauconnier, Gilles &
Mark Turner. The Way We Think: Conceptual Blending and the Mind’s Hidden
Complexities. 2002. Basic Books. Pp. 131-2.
“... mind is paradigmatically manifested in informed engagement in
action-feedback-evaluation-action loops in the environment.” Murphy,
Nancey & Warren Brown. Did My Neurons Make Me Do It?: Philosophical and
Neurobiological Perspectives on Moral Responsibility and Free Will. 2007.
Oxford Univ. Press. P. 11.
“Philosopher of science Donald Campbell has crafted an account of how a
larger system of causal factors can exert downward efficacy on selection
in producing the remarkably efficient jaw structures of worker termites
and ants:
“‘Consider the anatomy of the jaws of a worker termite or ant. The hinge
surfaces and the muscle attachments agree with Archimedes’ laws of levers,
that is, with macromechanics. They are optimally designed to apply maximum
force at a useful distance from the hinge ... This is a kind of conformity
to physics, but a different kind than is involved in the molecular,
atomic, strong and weak coupling processes underlying the formation of the
particular proteins of the muscle and shell of which the system is
constructed. The laws of levers are one part of the complex selective
system operating at the level of whole organisms. Selection at that level
has optimised viability, and has thus optimised the form of parts of
organisms, for the worker termite and ant and for their solitary
ancestors. We need the laws of levers, and organism-level selection... to
explain the particular distribution of proteins found in the jaw and hence
the DNA templates guiding their production ... Even the hence of the
previous sentence implies a reverse-directional ‘cause’ in that, by
natural selection, it is protein efficacy that determines which DNA
templates are present, even though the immediate micro determination is
from DNA to protein.’
“Campbell provides this example to illustrate the following set of theses:
“(1) All processes at the higher levels are restrained by and act in
conformity to the laws of lower levels, including the levels of subatomic
physics.
“(2) The teleonomic achievements at higher levels require for their
implementation specific lower-level mechanisms and processes. Explanation
is not complete until these micromechanisms have been specified.
“But in addition:
“(3) (The emergentist principle) Biological evolution in its meandering
exploration of segments of the universe encounters laws, operating as
selective systems, which are not described by the laws of physics and
inorganic chemistry, and which will not be described by the future
substitutes for the present approximations of physics and inorganic
chemistry.
“(4) (Downward causation) Where natural selection operates through life
and death at a higher level of organisation, the laws of the higher-level
selective system determine in part the distribution of lower-level events
and substances. Description of an intermediate-level phenomenon is not
completed by describing its possibility and implementation in lower-level
terms. Its presence, prevalence or distribution (all needed for a complete
explanation of biological phenomena) will often require reference to laws
at a higher level of organisation as well. Paraphrasing Point 1, all
processes at the lower levels of a hierarchy are restrained by and act in
conformity to the laws of the higher levels.” Murphy, Nancey & Warren
Brown. Did My Neurons Make Me Do It?: Philosophical and Neurobiological
Perspectives on Moral Responsibility and Free Will. 2007. Oxford Univ.
Press. Pp. 57-8. Subquote is from Campbell, Donald. 1974. “‘Downward Causation’
in Hierarchically Organised Biological Systems,” from Ayala, F. & T.
Dobzhansky (eds), Studies in the Philosophy of Biology, Pp. 179-186, P. 181.
“... nature can tangle causal chains into complex knots. Emergence is
about the topology of causality” Deacon, Terrence. “Three Levels of
Emergent Phenomena.” Murphy, Nancey and W. Stoeger (eds.). Evolution and
Emergence: Systems, Organisms, Persons. Oxford University Press. 2007. P.
94. Quoted in: Murphy, Nancey & Warren Brown. Did My Neurons Make Me Do
It?: Philosophical and Neurobiological Perspectives on Moral
Responsibility and Free Will. 2007. Oxford Univ. Press. P. 80.
“Note that the reductionist’s question is: if you take all the components
and place them in exactly the same positions in the environment and allow
the system to run again, will the entire system follow exactly the same
path? The reductionist assumes that it must do so unless there is some
source of genuine indeterminacy involved at the bottom level. The systems
theorist asks a different question: given that no two complex systems
(e.g., two ant colonies) are ever identical, why is it the case that,
starting from so wide a variety of initial conditions, one finds such
similar patterns emerging?” Murphy, Nancey & Warren Brown. Did My Neurons
Make Me Do It?: Philosophical and Neurobiological Perspectives on Moral
Responsibility and Free Will. 2007. Oxford Univ. Press. P. 98.
“Research has shown that merely perceiving the actions of others increases
the likelihood of performing the same acts.” Murphy, Nancey & Warren
Brown. Did My Neurons Make Me Do It?: Philosophical and Neurobiological
Perspectives on Moral Responsibility and Free Will. 2007. Oxford Univ.
Press. P. 119.
“Behavioral goals are elicited automatically in situations on the basis of
previous experiences in similar situations. A simple example can be seen
in what happens when a student enters a classroom. The goal of finding a
place to sit is automatically activated.” Murphy, Nancey & Warren Brown.
Did My Neurons Make Me Do It?: Philosophical and Neurobiological
Perspectives on Moral Responsibility and Free Will. 2007. Oxford Univ.
Press. P. 119.
“Mental states are essentially contextualized and, a fortiori, a mental
property should not be expected to reduce to the brain processes that
realize it.” Murphy, Nancey & Warren Brown. Did My Neurons Make Me Do It?:
Philosophical and Neurobiological Perspectives on Moral Responsibility and
Free Will. 2007. Oxford Univ. Press. P. 194.
In Alicia Juarrero’s terms, conditioning changes the probability matrix
for spreading neural activation.” Murphy, Nancey & Warren Brown. Did My
Neurons Make Me Do It?: Philosophical and Neurobiological Perspectives on
Moral Responsibility and Free Will. 2007. Oxford Univ. Press. P. 204.
Reference is to Juarrero, Alicia. Dynamics in Action: Intentional Behavior
as a Complex System. 1999. MIT Press.
“Let us restrict attention to properties that reduce in the sense of
having a physical realization, as in the cases of being a calculator,
having a certain temperature, and being a piece of money. Whether or not
an object counts as having properties such as these will depend, not only
on the physical properties of that object, but on various circumstances of
the context. Intensions of relevant language users constitute a plausible
candidate for relevant circumstances. In at least many cases, dependence
on context arises because the property constitutes a functional property,
where the relevant functional system (calculational practices, heat
transfer, monetary systems) are much larger than the property-bearing
object in question. These examples raise the question of whether many and
perhaps all mental properties depend ineliminably on relations to things
outside the organisms that have the mental properties.” Teller, Paul.
“Reduction.” From Audi (editor). Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy. Pp.
679-680. P. 680. Quoted in Murphy, Nancey & Warren Brown. Did My Neurons
Make Me Do It?: Philosophical and Neurobiological Perspectives on Moral
Responsibility and Free Will. 2007. Oxford Univ. Press. P. 208.
“If we are right about the inherent action-relevance of (much of) mental
life, then the problem of mental causation must be illusory.” Murphy,
Nancey & Warren Brown. Did My Neurons Make Me Do It?: Philosophical and
Neurobiological Perspectives on Moral Responsibility and Free Will. 2007.
Oxford Univ. Press. Pp. 215-6.
“As we have argued, the primary causal role of consciousness is to provide
information relevant to an organism’s action. Consciousness provides
flexibility in modulating one’s behavior that is not available to more
primitive organisms.” Murphy, Nancey & Warren Brown. Did My Neurons Make
Me Do It?: Philosophical and Neurobiological Perspectives on Moral
Responsibility and Free Will. 2007. Oxford Univ. Press. P. 219.
“Many take the problem of mental causation to be intrinsically insoluble
because of the traditional understanding that acting for a reason is
necessarily to be contrasted with being caused to act. Notice, though,
that much of the technological scaffolding upon which our higher cognitive
processes depend is designed so that its causal processes realize rational
transitions. A calculator, for example, is built so that its deterministic
internal processes produce true answers.” Murphy, Nancey & Warren Brown.
Did My Neurons Make Me Do It?: Philosophical and Neurobiological
Perspectives on Moral Responsibility and Free Will. 2007. Oxford Univ.
Press. Pp. 229-30.
“Michael Lewis reports on the development in children of ‘self-evaluative
emotions’ – shame, pride, guilt, and embarrassment. These emotions occur
later in life than more basic emotions such as fear and joy (at 2 ½ to 3
years of age) since they require a sense of self and recognition of
standards.” Murphy, Nancey & Warren Brown. Did My Neurons Make Me Do It?:
Philosophical and Neurobiological Perspectives on Moral Responsibility and
Free Will. 2007. Oxford Univ. Press. P. 253. Reference is to Lewis.
“Emergence of Consciousness and its Role in Human Development.” From
LeDoux et al (eds.) The Self: From Soul to Brain. Annals of the NY Academy
of Sciences. 1001. 2003. Pp. 121-125.
“A propensity is defined as ‘an irregular or non-necessitating causal
disposition of an object or system to produce some result or effect ...
usually conceived of as essentially probabilistic in nature.’ Karl Popper
regarded the existence of propensities as a metaphysical hypothesis needed
to interpret probability claims about single cases.” Murphy, Nancey &
Warren Brown. Did My Neurons Make Me Do It?: Philosophical and
Neurobiological Perspectives on Moral Responsibility and Free Will. 2007.
Oxford Univ. Press. P. 276. Reference is to Popper, K. A World of
Propensities. 1990.
“In all but the most rudimentary organisms, the success or failure of an
action changes the probability matrix according to which future behaviors
will be emitted. This is a downward effect, from the system that is the
whole organism acting in its environment, to the components of the nervous
system that channel behavioral options.” Murphy, Nancey & Warren Brown.
Did My Neurons Make Me Do It?: Philosophical and Neurobiological
Perspectives on Moral Responsibility and Free Will. 2007. Oxford Univ.
Press. Pp. 276-7.
“Both of Juarrero and Alwyn Scott favor reinstating all of Aristotle’s
four causes. Scott identifies triggering causes as efficient, structuring
causes and boundary conditions as formal causes. Juarrero describes an
attractor as a rudimentary precursor of a final cause.” Murphy, Nancey &
Warren Brown. Did My Neurons Make Me Do It?: Philosophical and
Neurobiological Perspectives on Moral Responsibility and Free Will. 2007.
Oxford Univ. Press. Note on P. 290. A. Scott’s reference is listed as a
personal communication while Juarrero’s is from her book Dynamics in
Action. MIT Press. 1999. P. 127.
“According to active externalism, it is that very interaction between
organism and environment from which ‘mind’ emerges.
“A wide adoption of this externalist concept of mind would have profound
and far-reaching consequences for society. Much more than just reshaping
the theories and experimental methods of cognitive psychology and
cognitive science, externalism legitimates the concepts of distributed
cognition, transactive memory systems, intersubjectivity manifolds, and
the collective mind. Moreover, externalism promises new and different
applied understandings of social behavior, group decision making, and even
personal relationships. For example, when you spend time with a group from
a different demographic background, you don’t just wind up acting like
someone else, you are someone else. For a couple to ‘be one’ becomes more
than a pleasing metaphor, it becomes a scientifically viable statement of
fact. Externalism also has implications for treatments of culture,
explaining how a tradition or fashion or sociological pattern might
literally ‘have a mind of its own.’” Spivey, Michael. The Continuity of
Mind. 2007. Oxford University Press. Pp. 304-5.
“Yet although embodied cognitive scientists do call on representations to
explain behavior, they call on them in such a way that the need for mental
gymnastics is reduced. The representations they call on are
indexical-functional, pushmi-pullyu, action-oriented, or emulator
representations. In what follows, I will refer to these collectively with
Clark’s term action-oriented representations. Action-oriented
representations differ from representations in earlier computationalist
theories of mind in that they represent things in a nonneutral way, as
geared to an animal’s actions, as affordances.” Chemero, Anthony. Radical
Embodied Cognitive Science. 2009. MIT Press. P. 26.
“The products of perceptual activity, it seems, are not always
action-neutral descriptions of external reality. They may instead
constitute direct recipes for acting and intervening. We thus glimpse
something of the shape of what Churchland et al describe as a framework
that is ‘motocentric’; rather than ‘visuocentric.’” Clark, Andy. “Where
Brain, Body and World Collide.” 2008. Pp. 1-18. From Knappet, Carl & L.
Malafouris, Ed. Material Agency: Towards a Non-Anthropocentric Approach.
Springer. P. 9. Reference is to Churchland, P., Ramachandran, V., &
Sejnowski, T. 1994. “A critique of pure vision.” In Koch & Davis (Eds.).
Large-Scale Neuronal Theories of the Brain. MIT Press.
“The external world is analogous to computer memory. When fixating a
location the 19 neurons that are linked to the fovea refer to information
computed from that location. Changing gaze is analogous to changing the
memory reference in a silicon computer.” Clark, Andy. “Where Brain, Body
and World Collide.” 2008. Pp. 1-18. From Knappet, Carl & L. Malafouris,
Ed. Material Agency: Towards a Non-Anthropocentric Approach. Springer. P.
12.
“The human mind, viewed through this special lens [the “work on
embodiment, action, and cognitive extension”], emerges at the productive
interface of brains, body, and social and material world.” Clark, Andy.
Supersizing the Mind: Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive Extension. 2008.
Oxford University Press. Pp. 218-19. [the word “through” is actually
printed in the original as “though” but I have chosen to ignore this
apparent typo.]
“Normally what is generated by a brain is a single, well-unified conscious
subject, but under special conditions, as seen in commissurotomy and
multiple personality, the consciousness can divide or fragment.”
“Stating the proposed view in this way signals immediately that the view
is a form of emergentism. But emergentism comes in many different
varieties, and this is one of the stronger ones, holding that a new
individual, not composed of previously existing ‘stuff,’ is what emerges
from the right configuration of the brain and nervous system....”
“... Kim has also stated that emergentism has really been the predominant
view in philosophy of mind for several decades, though not always under
that name.” Hasker, William. “Persons and the Unity of Consciousness.” Pp.
175-190. From Koons, Robert & George Bealer, Editors. The Waning of
Materialism. 2010. Oxford University Press. Pp. 184-5.
“For the emergentist, the seeds of every emergent property and the
behavior it manifests are found within the world’s fundamental elements,
in the form of latent dispositions awaiting only the right context for
manifestation.” O’Connor, Timothy & John Churchill. “Nonreductive
Physicalism or Emergent Dualism? The Argument from Mental Causation.” Pp.
261-279. From Koons, Robert & George Bealer, Editors. The Waning of
Materialism. 2010. Oxford University Press. P. 278.
“Thus, certain mental properties appear to be (1) resistant to analysis in
terms of physical structural properties and so plausibly ontologically
basic; (2) causally efficacious; and (3) borne only by highly organized
and complex systems. Though we cannot argue the matter at length here, we
find extant materialist attempts to overcome this prima facie case to be
implausible. (It goes without saying that we take the grounds for an
emergentist account of the mental to be defeasible.)” O’Connor, Timothy &
John Churchill. “Nonreductive Physicalism or Emergent Dualism? The
Argument from Mental Causation.” Pp. 261-279. From Koons, Robert & George
Bealer, Editors. The Waning of Materialism. 2010. Oxford University Press.
P. 279.
“The meanings of elements of multimodal interactions are not properties of
the elements themselves, but are emergent properties of the system of
relations among the elements. [Example here is of gestures in the air with
talking for lines of position over a chart]” Hutchins, Edwin. “The
Distributed Cognition Perspective on Human Interaction.” Pp. 375-398. From
Enfield, N. & S. Levinson. 2006. Roots of Human Sociality: Culture,
Cognition and Interaction. Berg. P. 381.
“Our folk theories assume that thought precedes action. I have tried to
show that in some activity settings, acting in the world is thinking.
Finally, processes of cultural evolution can produce activity settings in
which simple courses of action can produce powerful cognitive processes.”
Hutchins, Edwin. “The Distributed Cognition Perspective on Human
Interaction.” Pp. 375-398. From Enfield, N. & S. Levinson. 2006. Roots of
Human Sociality: Culture, Cognition and Interaction. Berg. P. 391.
“Projecting the image of complex, multimodal, environmentally coupled
interaction into the past illuminates new possibilities for development.
Change can take place anywhere in the complex interaction system. This
means that one need not imagine that all mechanisms of change are lodged
inside individual organisms. Just as the image of complex multimodal
environmentally coupled interaction gives us a new place to look for the
sources of organization of ongoing behavior; it also gives a new place to
look for the developmental changes across phylogenetic time.” Hutchins,
Edwin. “The Distributed Cognition Perspective on Human Interaction.” Pp.
375-398. From Enfield, N. & S. Levinson. 2006. Roots of Human Sociality:
Culture, Cognition and Interaction. Berg. P. 393.
“It is commonly assumed that genetic adaptations must produce a brain that
is capable of the hypothesized new functional abilities. What evolves,
however, is not the brain alone, but the system of brains, bodies, and
shared environments in interaction.” Hutchins, Edwin. “The Distributed
Cognition Perspective on Human Interaction.” Pp. 375-398. From Enfield, N.
& S. Levinson. 2006. Roots of Human Sociality: Culture, Cognition and
Interaction. Berg. P. 393.
“The study of human evolution remains committed to a Cartesian model of
cognition and consciousness in which the process of thinking is abstracted
from its real-world context.” Coward, Fiona & C. Gamble. “Big brains,
small worlds: material culture and the evolution of the mind.” 2008.
Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B. 363: 1969-1979. P.
1969.
“When two people join together in a task, they often act as one functional
unit, and the dyad that they form often has a different range of
behavioral possibilities than either individual alone. The decision to
engage in a joint action, including the means by which to carry it out,
may depend on each individual’s ability to perceive the affordances for
the resulting dyad, including the boundaries between actions that the dyad
can and cannot perform.” Davis, Tehran, M. Riley, K. Shockley & S.
Cummins-Sebree. “Perceiving affordances for joint actions.” 2010.
Perception. Vol. 39: 1624-44. P. 1639.
“Findings from a number of recent studies have established that people are
indeed able to make perceptual judgments of what the environment affords
others with a high degree of accuracy.... “ Davis, Tehran, M. Riley, K.
Shockley & S. Cummins-Sebree. “Perceiving affordances for joint actions.”
2010. Perception. Vol. 39: 1624-44. P. 1642.
Authors & Works cited in this section:
Aristotle.
Psychology
Chemero, Anthony. Radical Embodied Cognitive Science.
Clark, Andy & Chalmers, David. "The Extended Mind."
Clark, Andy, Being There: Putting brain, Body, and World Together
Clark, Andy. Supersizing the Mind: Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive
Extension
Clark, Andy. "Where Brain, Body and World Collide."
Coward, Fiona & C. Gamble. “Big brains, small worlds: material culture and
the evolution
Cziko, Gary. Without Miracles: Universal Selection Theory and
Davis, Tehran et al. “Perceiving affordances for joint actions.
Dennett, Daniel, Consciousness Explained
Donald, Merlin. Origins of the Modern Mind
Dyson, George. Darwin among the Machines: The Evolution of Global
Intelligence
Edelman, Gerald and Tononi, Giulio. A Universe of Consciousness
Edelman, Gerald, Bright Air, Brilliant Fire; on the Matter of
Fauconnier, Gilles & Mark Turner. The Way We Think: Conceptual Blending
and the Mind’s Hidden Complexities
Gladwell, Malcolm. Blink: The Power of Thinking Without Thinking
Godfrey-Smith, Peter. Complexity and the Function of Mind in Nature
Griffin, David Ray. Unsnarling the World-Knot: Consciousness,
Griffiths, Paul E. What Emotions Really Are
Hutchins, Edwin. “The Distributed Cognition Perspective on Human
Interaction.”
Johnson, Mark & George Lakoff. Philosophy in the Flesh: The Embodied
Kant, I., Preface to the Critique of Pure Reason
Koons, Robert & George Bealer, Editors. The Waning of Materialism
Murphy, Nancey & Warren Brown. Did My Neurons Make Me Do It?
Plotkin, Henry. The Imagined World Made Real: Towards a Natural
Reed, Edward S. Encountering the World: Toward an Ecological
Rockwell, W. Teed. Neither Brain nor Ghost: A Nondualist Alternative
Samson, Paul and David Pitt. The Biosphere and Noosphere Reader
Spivey, Michael. The Continuity of Mind.
Taylor, Mark C. The Moment of Complexity: Emerging Network Culture
Tomasello, Michael. The Cultural Origins of Human Cognition
Wallace, B. Alan. The Taboo of Subjectivity: Toward a New Science
Wilson, Robert A. Boundaries of the Mind: The Individual in the